If Materialism
Is True, the United States Is Probably Conscious
Eric Schwitzgebel
Department of Philosophy
University of California at Riverside
Riverside, CA
92521
eschwitz at domain:
ucr.edu
February 8, 2013
If
Materialism Is True, the United States Is Probably Conscious
Abstract:
If
you’re a materialist, you probably think that rabbits are conscious. And you ought to think that. After all, rabbits are a lot like us,
biologically and neurophysiologically. If you’re a materialist, you probably also
think that conscious experience would be present in a wide range of naturally-evolved
alien beings behaviorally very similar to us even if they are physiologically
very different. And you ought to think
that. After all, to deny it seems
insupportable Earthly chauvinism. But a
materialist who accepts consciousness in weirdly formed aliens ought also to
accept consciousness in spatially distributed group entities. If she then also accepts rabbit
consciousness, she ought to accept the possibility of consciousness even in
rather dumb group entities. Finally, the
United States would seem to be a rather dumb group entity of the relevant
sort. If we set aside our morphological
prejudices against spatially distributed group entities, we can see that the
United States has all the types of properties that materialists tend to regard
as characteristic of conscious beings.
Keywords:
metaphysics, consciousness, phenomenology, group mind, superorganism,
collective consciousness, metaphilosophy
If Materialism
Is True, the United States Is Probably Conscious
If
materialism is true, the reason you
have a stream of conscious experience – the reason there’s something it’s like
to be you while there’s (presumably!) nothing it’s like to be a toy robot or a
bowl of chicken soup, the reason you possess what Anglophone philosophers call phenomenology – is that the material
stuff out of which you are made is organized the right way. You might find materialism attractive if you
reject the thought that people are animated by immaterial spirits or possess
immaterial properties.[1]
Here’s another thought you might reject:
The United States is literally, like you, phenomenally conscious. That is, the United States, conceived of as a
spatially distributed, concrete entity with people as some or all of its parts,
literally possesses a stream of conscious experience over and above the
experiences of its members considered individually. In this essay, I will argue that accepting
the materialist idea that you probably like (if you’re a typical early
21st-century philosopher) should draw you to accept some group consciousness
ideas you probably don’t like (if you’re a typical early 21st-century
philosopher) – unless you choose, instead, to accept some other ideas you
probably ought to like even less.
The argument in brief is this. If you’re a materialist, you probably think
that rabbits have conscious experience.
And you ought to think that.
After all, rabbits are a lot like us, biologically and neurophysiologically.
If you’re a materialist, you probably also think that conscious
experience would be present in a wide range of naturally-evolved alien beings
behaviorally very similar to us even if they are physiologically very
different. And you ought to think
that. After all, to deny it seems
insupportable Earthly chauvinism. But, I
will argue, a materialist who accepts consciousness in weirdly formed aliens
ought also to accept consciousness in spatially distributed group
entities. If she then also accepts
rabbit consciousness, she ought to accept the possibility of consciousness even
in rather dumb group entities. Finally,
the United States would seem to be a rather dumb group entity of the relevant
sort. (Or maybe, even, it’s rather
smart, but that’s more than I need for my argument.) If we set aside our morphological prejudices
against spatially distributed group entities, we can see that the United States
has all the types of properties that materialists tend to regard as
characteristic of conscious beings.
Of course it’s utterly bizarre to
suppose that the United States is literally phenomenally conscious.[2] But how good an objection is that? Cosmology is bizarre. Microphysics is bizarre. Higher mathematics is bizarre. The more we discover about the fundamentals
of the world, the weirder things seem to become. Should metaphysics be so different? Our sense of strangeness is no rigorous index
of reality.[3]
My claim is conditional and gappy. If materialism is true, probably the United States is
conscious. Alternatively, if materialism
is true, the most natural thing to
conclude is that the United States is conscious.
1. Sirian Supersquids, Antarean Antheads, and Your Own Horrible Contiguism.
We are deeply prejudiced beings. Whites are prejudiced against blacks;
Gentiles against Jews; overestimators against underestimators.[4] Even when we intellectually reject such
prejudices, they permeate our behavior and our implicit assumptions.[5] If we ever meet interplanetary travelers
similar to us in overall intelligence and moral character, we will likely be
prejudiced against them too, especially if they look weird.
It’s hard to imagine a prejudice more
deeply ingrained than our prejudice against entities that are visibly spatially
discontinuous – a prejudice built, perhaps, even into the basic functioning of
our visual system.[6] Analogizing to racism, sexism, and speciesism, let’s call such prejudice contiguism.
You might think that so-called contiguism is always justified and thus undeserving of a
pejorative label. You might think, for
example, that spatial contiguity is a necessary condition of objecthood or entityhood, so that
it makes no more sense to speak of a spatially discontinuous entity than it
makes sense – unless you adopt some liberal views about ontology[7] –
to speak of an entity composed of your left shoe, the Eiffel Tower, and the
rings of Saturn. If you’ll excuse me for
saying so, that attitude is foolish provincialism. Let me introduce you to two of my favorite
non-Earthly species.
The
Sirian supersquids. In the oceans of a planet around Sirius lives
a naturally-evolved animal with a central head and a thousand tentacles. It’s a very smart animal – as smart, as
linguistic, as artistic and creative as human beings are, though the
superficial forms of its language and art differ from ours. Let’s call these animals “supersquids”.
The supersquid’s
brain is not centrally located like our own.
Rather, the supersquid
brain is distributed mostly among nodes in its thousand tentacles, while its
head houses digestive and reproductive organs and the like. Despite the spatial distribution of its
cognitive processes across its body, however, the supersquid’s
cognition is fully integrated, and supersquids report
having a single, unified stream of experience.
Part of what enables their cognitive and phenomenal integration is this:
Rather than having relatively slow electrochemical nerves, supersquid
nerves are reflective capillaries carrying light signals, something like
Earthly fiber optics. The speed of these
signals ensures the tight temporal synchrony of the cognitive activity shooting
among its tentacular nodes.
The supersquids
show all external signs of consciousness.
They have covertly visited Earth, and one is a linguist who has mastered
English well enough to ace the Turing test (Turing 1950): He can be, when he
wants to, indistinguishable in verbal behavior from a normal adult human
being. Like us, the supersquids
have communities of philosophers and psychologists who write eloquently about
the metaphysics of consciousness, about emotional phenomenology, about their
imagery and dreams. Any unbiased alien
observer looking at Earth and looking at the supersquid home planet would see no good grounds for
ascribing consciousness to us but not them.
Some supersquid
philosophers doubt that Earthly beings are genuinely phenomenally conscious,
given our radically different physiological structure (“What? Chemical nerves? How protozoan!”).
However, I’m glad to report that only a small minority holds that view.
Here’s another interesting feature of supersquids: They can detach their limbs. To be detachable, a supersquid limb must be able to maintain homeostasis
briefly on its own and suitable light-signal transceivers must appear on the
surface of the limb and on the bodily surface to which the limb is normally
attached. Once the squids began down
this evolutionary path, selective advantages nudged them farther along, revolutionizing
their hunting and foraging. Two major
subsequent adaptations were these: First, the nerve signals between the head
and limb-surface transceivers shifted to wavelengths less readily degraded by
water and obstacles. Second, the
limb-surface transceivers developed the ability to communicate directly among
themselves without needing to pass signals through the central head. Since the speed of light is negligible, supersquids can now detach arbitrarily limbs and send them
roving widely across the sea with hardly any disruption of their cognitive
processing. The energetic costs are
high, but they supplement their diet and use technological aids.
In this limb-roving condition, the supersquids’ limbs are not wandering independently under
local limb-only control, then reporting back.
Limb-roving squids remain as cognitively integrated as do non-roving
squids and as intimately in control of their entire spatially-distributed
selves. Despite all the spatial
intermixing of their limbs with those of other supersquids,
each individual’s cognitive processes remain private because each squid’s
transceivers employ a distinctive signature wavelength. If a limb is lost, a new limb can be
artificially grown and fitted, though losing too many limbs at once can
substantially impair memory and cognitive function. The supersquids have
begun to experiment with limb exchange and cross-compatible transceiver
signals. This has led them toward
radically Parfitian views of personal identity, and
they are re-envisioning the possibilities of marriage, team sports, and
scientific collaboration.[8]
I hope you’ll agree with me, and with
the universal opinion of supersquids, that supersquids are coherent entities. Despite their spatial discontinuity, they
aren’t arbitrary collections. They are
integrated systems that can be treated as beings of the sort that might house
consciousness. And if they might, they
do. Or so you should probably say if
you’re a mainline philosophical materialist.
After all, supersquids are naturally evolved
beings that act and speak and write and philosophize just like we do.
Does it matter that this is only science
fiction? I hope you’ll agree that supersquids, or entities relevantly similar, are at least physically possible. And if such entities are physically possible,
and if the universe is as large as most cosmologists currently think it is –
maybe even infinite, maybe even one among an infinite number of infinite
universes![9] – then it might not be a bad bet that some such spatially
distributed intelligences are actual.
Biology can be provincial, maybe, but not metaphysics; you’d better have
room in your metaphysics for supersquids.
The
Antarean antheads. On the surface of a planet around Antares lives a species of animals who look like woolly
mammoths but who act much like human beings. I have gazed into my crystal ball and this is
what I see: Tomorrow, they visit Earth.
They watch our television shows, learn our language, and politely ask to
tour our lands. It turns out that they
are sanitary, friendly, excellent conversationalists, and well supplied with
rare metals for trade, so they are welcomed across the globe. They are quirky in a few ways, however. For example, their cognitive activity takes
them on average ten times longer to execute.
This has no overall effect on their intelligence, but it does test the
patience of conversation partners unaccustomed to the Antareans’
slow pace. They also find some tasks
easy that we find difficult and vice versa.
They are baffled and amused by our trouble with simple logic problems
like the Wason Selection Task (Wason
1968) and tensor calculus, but they are impressed by our skill in integrating
auditory and visual information.
Over time, some Antareans
migrate permanently down from their orbiting ship. Patchy accommodations are made for their size
and speed, and they start to attend our schools and join our corporations. Some achieve political office and display
approximately the normal human range of vices.
Although Antareans don’t reproduce by coitus,
they find some forms of physical contact arousing and have broadly human
attitudes toward pair-bonding. Marriage
equality is achieved. What a model of
interplanetary harmony! Ordinary
non-philosophers all agree, of course, that Antareans
are conscious.
Here’s why I call them “antheads”: Their heads and humps contain not neurons but
rather ten million squirming insects, each a fraction of a millimeter across. Each insect has a complete set of minute
sensory organs and a nervous system of its own, and the antheads’
behavior arises from complex patterns of interaction among these individually
dumb insects. These mammoth creatures
are much-evolved descendants of Antarean ant colonies
that evolved in symbiosis with a brainless, living hive. The interior insects’ interactions are so informationally efficient that neighboring insects can
respond differentially to the behavioral or chemical effects of other insects’
individual outgoing efferent nerve impulses.
The individual ants vary in size, structure, sensa,
and mobility. Specialist ants have
various affinities, antagonisms, and predilections, but no ant individually
approaches human intelligence. No
individual ant, for example, has an inkling of Shakespeare despite the Antareans’ great appreciation of Shakespeare’s work.
There seems to be no reason in principle
that such an entity couldn’t execute any computational function that a human
brain could execute or satisfy any high-level functional description that the
human organism could satisfy. All the
creativity of literary interpretation, all the cleverness of humor and
weirdness of visual art, should be available to the antheads
on standard materialist approaches to cognition.
Maybe there are little spatial gaps
between the ants. Does it matter? Maybe, in the privacy of their homes, the
ants sometimes disperse from the body, exiting and entering through the
mouth. Does it matter? Maybe if the exterior body is too severely
injured, the ants recruit a new body from nutrient tanks – and when they march
off to do this, they retain some cognitive coordination, able to remember and
report thoughts they had mid-transfer. They
reconvene and say, “Oh it’s such a free and airy feeling to be without a
body! And yet it’s a fearful thing
too. It’s good to feel again the power
of limbs and mouth. May this new body
last long and well.
Shall we dance, then, love?”
We humans are not so different perhaps. In one
perspective (e.g., Maynard Smith and Szathmáry 1995)
we ourselves are but symbiotic aggregates of simpler organisms that invested in
cooperation.
2. Anti-Nesting Principles.
You might object to the Antarean antheads even if you’re
okay with the Sirian supersquids. You might think that the individual ants
would or could be individually conscious and that it’s impossible for one
conscious organism to be constituted by other conscious organisms. Some theoreticians of consciousness have said
such things – though I’ve never seen a good justification of this view.
Hilary Putnam (1965), for example,
simply stipulates: No organism capable of feeling pain possesses a decomposition into parts which are separately capable of
feeling pain. Putnam offers no argument
for this stipulation apart from the fact that he wants to rule out the
apparently absurd possibility of “swarms of bees as single pain-feelers” (p.
163). Putnam doesn’t explain why this
possibility is absurd for actual swarms of bees, much less why no possible
future evolutionary development of a swarm of conscious bees could ever also be
a single pain-feeler. It seems a danglingly unjustified exception to his otherwise clean
functionalism.
Giulio
Tononi (forthcoming) also advances an anti-nesting
principle. On Tononi’s
theory of consciousness, consciousness arises whenever information is
integrated; and whenever one informationally
integrated system is nested in another, consciousness occurs only at the level
of organization that integrates the most
information – what he calls the “exclusion principle”. Tononi defends the
exclusion principle by appeal to Occam’s razor, with intuitive support from the
apparent absurdity of supposing that group consciousness could emerge from two
people talking.[10] But it’s unclear why Tononi
should put any weight on intuitive resistance to group consciousness, given his
near panpsychism: He defends the idea that a
photodiode or an OR-gate could have a single bit’s worth of consciousness (Tononi 2004, 2008, 2012; Balduzzi
and Tononi 2009).
Why not some such low-level consciousness from the group, too? And Occam’s razor is a tricky implement. Although admitting the existence of
unnecessary entities seems like a bad idea, what’s an “entity” and what’s
“unnecessary” is often unclear, especially in part-whole cases. Is a hydrogen atom unnecessary once one
admits the proton and electron into one’s ontology? What makes it necessary, or not, to admit the
existence of consciousness in the first place?
It’s obscure why the necessity of admitting consciousness to Antarean antheads should depend
on whether it’s also necessary to admit consciousness among the individual ants.
Anti-nesting principles, though
seemingly designed to avoid counterintuitive implications of group consciousness,
bring different counterintuitive consequences in their train. As Ned Block (1978/1991) argues against
Putnam, such principles appear to have the unintuitive consequence that if
ultra-tiny conscious organisms were somehow to become incorporated into your
brain – perhaps, for reasons unbeknownst to you, each choosing to play the role
of one neuron or one part of one neuron – you would be rendered nonconscious, despite the fact that all your behavior,
including self-reports of consciousness, might remain the same. Tononi’s principle
also seems to imply that if there were a large enough election, organized the
right way with enough different ballot measures, the resulting polity-level
informational integration would eclipse the informational integration of the
main conscious stream in the human brain, and thus the individual voters would
all lose consciousness. Perhaps we are
already on the verge of this in California?[11] Furthermore, since “greater than” is a
dichotomous property and not a matter of degree, there ought on Tononi’s view to be an exact point at which polity-level
integration causes human level consciousness suddenly to vanish (see esp. Tononi 2010, note 9).
There ought to be a point at which the addition of a single voter would
cause the loss of consciousness in all individual voters – even without any
detectable behavioral or self-report effects, or any loss of integration, at
the level of individual voters. It seems
odd to suppose that so much, and simultaneously so little, could turn on the
discovery of a single mail-in ballot.
3. Dumbing Down
and Smarting Up.
If you’re a materialist, you probably
think that rabbits are phenomenally conscious – that is, that “there’s
something it’s like to be” a rabbit, that rabbits experience pain, have visual
experiences, and maybe have feelings like fear.
Some philosophers would deny rabbit consciousness; more on that
later. For purposes of this section,
I’ll assume you’re on board. And if you
accept rabbit consciousness, you probably ought also to accept the possibility
of consciousness in the Sirian and Antarean equivalents of rabbits.
One such species is the Sirian squidbits, a species with
cognitive processing distributed among detachable limbs but with approximately
the intelligence of Earthly rabbits.
When chased by predators, the squidbits will
sometimes eject their thousand limbs in different directions and hide their central
heads. Most Sirians
regard squidbits as conscious entities; whatever
reasoning justifies attributing consciousness to Earthly rabbits similarly
justifies attributing consciousness to Sirian squidbits. A analogous story also holds on Antares.
Let me tie Sirius, Antares,
and Earth a bit more tightly together.
Gazing into the distant future on Sirius I see this: The central body of
the squidbit becomes smaller and smaller – thus
easier to hide – and the limbs develop more independent homeostatic and
nutritional capacities, until the primary function of the central body is just
reproduction of these increasingly independent limbs. Earthly entomologists come to refer to these
heads as “queens”. Still later, squidbits enter into symbiotic relationship with brainless
but mobile hives, and the thousand bits learn to hide within for safety. These mobile hives look something like woolly
mammoths. Where is the sharp, principled
line between group and individual?
We can increase the size Antareans and the intelligence of the ants. Maybe Antareans are
the size of houses and filled with naked mole rats. This wouldn’t seem to affect the
argument. Maybe the ants or rats can
even have human levels of intelligence, while the Antareans’
behavior still emerges in roughly the same way from the system as a whole. Again, this wouldn’t seem to affect the
argument.
The present view might seem to conflict
with “type-materialist” views that equate human consciousness with specific
biological processes.[12] I don’t think it does conflict, however. Most type-materialist accounts allow that
weird alien species might have conscious experiences. Maybe the phenomenal experience of feeling
pain, for example, is identical to different types of physical states in
different species. Or maybe the
phenomenal type pain really requires
Earthly neurons but Antareans have conscious
experiences of schmain,
which feels very different but plays a broadly similar functional role. Or maybe radically different low-level
physical structures (neurons vs. light signals vs. squirming bugs) can count as
physically type-identical at a coarse or abstract level of description, or even
have to be, if they play similar
enough roles in undergirding the behavioral patterns.
4. A Telescopic View of the United
States.
A planet-sized alien who squints might
see the United States as a single diffuse entity consuming bananas and
automobiles, wiring up communications systems, touching the moon, and
regulating its smoggy exhalations – an entity that can be evaluated for the
presence or absence of consciousness.
You might say: The United States is not
a biological organism. It doesn’t have a
life cycle. It doesn’t reproduce. It’s not biologically integrated and
homeostatic. Therefore, it’s just not
the right type of thing to be
conscious.
To this concern I have two replies.
First, why should consciousness require
being an organism in the biological sense?
Properly-designed androids, brains in vats, gods – these things might
not be organisms in the biological sense and yet are sometimes thought to have
consciousness. (I’m assuming
materialism, but some materialists believe in actual or possible gods.) Having a distinctive mode of reproduction is
often thought to be a central, defining feature of organisms (e.g., Wilson 2005;
Godfrey-Smith 2009, forthcoming), but it’s unclear why reproduction should
matter to consciousness. Human beings
might vastly extend their lives and cease reproduction, or they might
conceivably transform themselves through technology so that any specific
condition on having a biological life cycle is dispensed with, while our brains
and behavior remain largely the same.
Would we no longer be conscious?
Being composed of cells and organs that share genetic material might
also be characteristic of an organism, but as with reproduction it’s unclear
what would justify regarding such composition as essential to mentality,
especially once we consider a variety of physically possible non-Earthly
creatures.
Second, it’s not clear that nations
aren’t biological organisms. The United
States is (after all) composed of
cells and organs that share genetic material, to the extent it is composed of
people who are composed of cells and organs and who share genetic
material. The United States also
maintains homeostasis. Farmers grow
crops to feed non-farmers, and these nutritional resources are distributed with
the help of other people via a network of roads. Groups of people organized as import
companies bring in food from the outside environment. Medical specialists help maintain the health
of their compatriots. Soldiers defend
against potential threats. Teachers
educate future generations. Home
builders, textile manufacturers, telephone companies, mail carriers, rubbish
haulers, bankers, police, all contribute to the stable
well-being of the organism. Politicians
and bureaucrats work top-down to ensure that certain actions are coordinated,
while other types of coordination emerge spontaneously from the bottom up, just
as in ordinary animals. Viewed
telescopically, the United States is a pretty awesome animal.[13] Now some parts of the United States also are
individually sophisticated and awesome, but that subtracts nothing from the
awesomeness of the U.S. as a whole – no more than we should be less awed by
human biology as we discover increasing evidence of our dependence on
microscopic symbionts.
Nations also reproduce – not sexually
but by fission. The United States and
several other countries are fission products of Great Britain. In the 1860s, the United States almost fissioned again. And
fissioning nations retain traits of the parent that
influence the fitness of future fission products – intergenerationally
stable developmental resources, if you will.
As in cellular fission, there’s a process by which subparts align into
different sides and then separate physically and functionally.
On Earth, at all levels, from the
molecular to the neural to the societal, there’s a vast array of competitive
and cooperative pressures; at all levels, there’s a wide range of actual and
possible modes of reproduction, direct and indirect; and all levels show
manifold forms of symbiosis, parasitism, partial integration, agonism, and antagonism.
There isn’t as radical a difference in kind as people are inclined to
think between our favorite level of organization and higher and lower levels.
5. What Is So Special About Brains?
According to materialism, what’s really special about us is our brains. Brains are what make us conscious. Maybe brains have this power on their own, so
that even a lone brain in an otherwise empty universe would have conscious
experience if it were structured in the right way; or maybe consciousness
arises not strictly from the brain itself but rather from a thoroughly
entangled mix of brain, body, and environment.[14] But all materialists agree: Brains are
central to the story.
Now what is so special about brains, on
the materialist view? Why do they give
rise to conscious experience while a similar mix of chemical elements in
chicken soup does not? It must be
something about how those elements are organized. Two general features of brain organization
stand out: their complex high order / low entropy information processing, and
their role in coordinating sophisticated responsiveness to environmental
stimuli. These two features are of course
related. Brains also arise from an evolutionary
and developmental history, within an environmental context, which might play a
constitutive (and not merely a causal) role in determining function and
cognitive content.[15] According to a broad class of plausible
materialist views, any system with sophisticated enough information processing
and environmental responsiveness, and perhaps the right kind of historical and
environmental embedding, should have conscious experience. My central claim is: The United States seems
to have what it takes, if standard materialist criteria are straightforwardly
applied without post-hoc noodling. It is mainly unjustified morphological
prejudice that blinds us to this.
Consider, first, the sheer quantity of
information transfer among members of the United States. The human brain contains about 1011
neurons exchanging information through an average of about 103
connections per neuron, firing at peak rates of about once every several
milliseconds. The United States, in
comparison, contains only about 3 x 108 people. But those people exchange a lot of
information. How much? We might begin by considering how much
information flows from one person to another via stimulation of the
retina. The human eye contains about 108
photoreceptor cells. Most people in the
United States spend most of their time in visual environments that are largely
created by the actions of people (including their own past selves). If we count even 1/300 of this visual
neuronal stimulation as the relevant sort of person-to-person information
exchange, then the quantity of visual connectedness among people is similar to
the neuronal connectedness within the human brain (1014
connections). Very little of the
exchanged information will make it past attentional
filters for further processing, but analogous considerations apply to
information exchange among neurons. Or
here’s another way to think about the issue: If at any time 1/300th of the U.S.
population is viewing internet video at 1 megabit per second, that’s a transfer
rate between people of 1012 bits per second in this one minor
activity alone.[16] Furthermore, it seems unlikely that conscious
experience requires achieving the degree of informational connectedness of the
entire neuronal structure of the human brain.
If mice are conscious, they manage it with under
108 neurons.
A more likely source of concern, it
seems to me, is that information exchange among members of the U.S. population
isn’t of the right type to engender a
genuine stream of conscious experience.
A simple computer download, even if it somehow managed to involve 1017
bits per second or more, presumably wouldn’t by itself alone do the job. For consciousness, there presumably needs to
be some organization of the information in the service of coordinated,
goal-directed responsiveness; and maybe, too, there needs to be some sort of
sophisticated self-monitoring.
But the United States has these
properties too. Our information exchange
is not in the form of a simply-structured massive internet download. The United States is a goal-directed entity,
flexibly self-protecting and self-preserving.
The United States responds, intelligently or semi-intelligently, to
opportunities and threats – not less intelligently, I think, than a small
mammal. The United States expanded west
as its population grew, developing mines and farmland in traditionally Native
American territory. When Al Qaeda struck
New York, the United States responded in a variety of ways, formally and
informally, in many branches and levels of government and in the populace as a
whole. Saddam Hussein shook his sword
and the United States invaded Iraq. The
U.S. acts in part through its army, and the army’s movements involve perceptual
or quasi-perceptual responses to inputs: The army moves around the mountain,
doesn’t crash into it. Similar, the spy
networks of the CIA detected the location of Osama bin Laden, whom the U.S.
then killed. The United States monitors
space for asteroids that might threaten Earth.
Is there less information, less coordination, less intelligence than in
a hamster? The Pentagon monitors the
actions of the Army, and its own actions.
The Census Bureau counts us. The
State Department announces the U.S. position on foreign affairs. The Congress passes a resolution declaring
that we hate tyranny and love apple pie.
This is self-representation.
Isn’t it? The United States is
also a social entity, communicating with other entities of its type. It wars against Germany then reconciles then
wars again. It threatens and monitors
Iran. It cooperates with other nations
in threatening and monitoring Iran. As
in other linguistic entities, some of its internal states are excellently known
and straightforwardly reportable to others (who just won the Presidential
election, its 2010 GDP) while others are not (how many foreign spies have
infiltrated the CIA, the reason Elvis Presley sells more albums than Ella
Fitzgerald).
One might think that for an entity to
have real, intrinsic representational content, meaningful utterances, and
intentionality, it must be richly historically embedded in the right kind of
environment. Lightning strikes a swamp
and “Swampman” congeals randomly by freak quantum
chance. Swampman
might utter sounds that we would be disposed to interpret as meaning “Wow, this
swamp is humid!”, but if he has no learning history or evolutionary history,
some have argued, this utterance would have no more meaning than a freak
occurrence of the same sounds by a random perturbance
of air.[17] But I see no grounds for objection here. The United States is no Swampman. The United States has long been embedded in a
natural and social environment, richly causally connected to the world beyond –
connected in a way that would seem to give meaning to its representations and
functions to its parts.
I am asking you to think of the United
States as a planet-sized alien might – or as a planet-sized group intelligence might
– that is, to evaluate the behaviors and capacities of the United States as a
concrete, spatially distributed entity with people as some or all of its parts,
an entity within which individual people play roles somewhat analogous to the
role that individual cells play in your body.
If you are willing to jettison contiguism and
other morphological prejudices, this is not, I think, an intolerably weird
perspective. As a house for
consciousness, a rabbit brain is not clearly more sophisticated. I leave it open whether we include as part of
the body of the U.S., or instead as part of its environment, objects like roads
and computers.
Maybe the actions, attitudes, and
representations of the United States are all ultimately reducible to the
actions, attitudes, and representations of U.S. citizens and residents, in some
complex combination. On that issue I
take no stand. (What does “reducible”
mean?) All that is required for this
part of my argument is that the United States actually engages in actions,
actually adopts attitudes, and actually formulates representations, whether
reducibly or not, of at least a mammalian level of sophistication. Perhaps, too, if materialists are right, all
your actions, attitudes, and representations are in some sense reducible to
other things; few philosophers conclude that this would make them unreal. When the United States imports oil from
countries A and B, rather than countries C and D, intelligently responding to
represented price, it is always individual people, organized in groups, and embedded
in a larger environment, who together import the oil. It is also individual cells in your brain,
organized in groups, that together respond to the
tilting angle of the visual stimulus, that together match the incoming signal
with the stored representation of grandma’s face. Great things emerge from contextually
embedded groups. My argument does not
turn on the irreducibility of group behavior or any ineliminable
explanatory necessity of appeals to the group level. Rather, my thought is this: There’s something
awesomely special about brains such that they give rise to consciousness, and
considered from a materialist perspective, the United States seems to be
awesomely special in just the same sorts of ways.
One might object that “the United
States” is an abstraction, like “the average Californian” or “the teenage
mind”. The average Californian may be
conscious, and the teenage mind may seethe with angst, but it would be an
absurd category mistake to suppose that therefore there exists some additional
stream of consciousness of the average Californian beyond the streams of
consciousness of each Californian considered individually, or some further bit
of angst in addition to all the individual angst of particular teenagers. This objection, however, forgets the
concreteness on which I have repeatedly insisted. I am willing to be somewhat flexible about
the best way to conceptualize the boundaries of the body of the United States,
but I insist that we consider the matter concretely, as a planet-sized alien
observer might. It’s
not like seeing all the buildings around campus and then seeking some
additional ghostly building which is “the university” (Ryle 1949). Rather, it’s like seeing all the buildings
around campus and then wondering what features, like open space between the
buildings, might be possessed by the campus as a whole but neglected by someone
with too narrow a focus on the individual parts.
What is it about brains, as hunks of matter, that makes them special enough to give rise to
consciousness? Looking in broad strokes
at the types of things materialists tend to say in answer – things like
sophisticated information processing and flexible, goal-directed environmental
responsiveness, things like representation, self-representation, multiply-ordered
layers of self-monitoring and information-seeking self-regulation, rich
functional roles, and a content-giving historical embeddedness
– it seems like the United States has all those same features. In fact, it seems to have them in a greater
degree than do some beings, like rabbits, that we ordinarily regard as
conscious.
What could be missing?
6. What Could Be Missing.
In this section, I would have liked to
apply particular, detailed materialist metaphysical theories to the question at
hand. It seems like the natural next
step! Unfortunately, I face four
obstacles, in combination nearly insurmountable. First: Few materialist theoreticians
explicitly consider the possibility of literal group consciousness.[18] Thus, it is a matter of speculation how
properly to apply their theory to a case that might have been overlooked in the
theory’s design and presentation.
Second: Many theories, especially those constructed by neuroscientists
and psychologists, implicitly or explicitly limit themselves to human or at most vertebrate
consciousness, and thus are silent about how consciousness would work in other
sorts of entities (e.g., Baars 1988; Crick
1994). Third: Further limiting the pool
of relevant theories is the fact that few thinkers really engage the
metaphysics from top to bottom. For
example, most theoreticians advocating “higher order” models of consciousness
don’t provide sufficient detail on the nature of “lower order” mental states
for me to evaluate whether the United States would qualify as having such
lower-order states (though if it does, it would probably have higher-order
states too).[19] Fourth: When I did arrive at what I thought
would be a representative sample of four prominent, metaphysically ambitious,
top-to-bottom theories of consciousness, it proved rather complex to assess how
each view applied to the case of the U.S. – too complex to
embed in an already long essay.[20] Thus, I think further progress on this issue
will require having some specific counterproposals to evaluate. In this section, I will address three
objections, one inferred from remarks by Andy Clark on the extended mind
hypothesis and two derived from email correspondence with prominent materialist
philosophers. In the next section, I
will explore three other ways of escaping my conclusion – ways that involve
rejecting either rabbit consciousness, alien consciousness, or both.
Objection:
high-bandwidth neural synchrony. Andy Clark (2009) has recently argued that
consciousness requires high bandwidth neural synchrony – a type of synchrony
that is not currently possible between the external environment and structures
interior to the human brain. Thus, he
says, consciousness stays in the head.
Now in the human case, and generally for Earthly animals with central
nervous systems, maybe Clark is right – and maybe such Earthly animals are all
he really has in view. But we can
consider elevating this principle to a necessity. The information integration of the brain is
arguably qualitatively different in this way from the informational integration
of the United States. If consciousness, in
general, as a matter of physics or metaphysics, requires massive, swift
parallelism, then maybe we can get mammal consciousness without U.S.
consciousness.
But this move has a steep price, if we
are concerned, as the ambitious materialist should be, about hypothetical and
alien cases. Suppose we were to discover
that some people, though outwardly very similar to us, or some alien species,
operated via incredibly swift serial processing rather than by parallel
processing. Would we really be justified
in thinking they had no conscious experience?
Or what if we were to discover a species of long-lived, planet-sized
aliens whose cognitive subprocesses, though operating
in parallel, proceeded much more slowly than ours, with transfer delays on the
order of hours rather than milliseconds?
If we’re going to adopt the same liberal spirit that admits
consciousness in Sirian supersquids
and Antarean antheads – the
most natural development of the materialist view, I’m inclined to think – it
seems that we can’t insist on high-bandwidth neural synchrony. If instead we adopt a more conservative view,
insisting on some particular architecture, it seems we need some principled
motivation for excluding from consciousness any hypothetical being that lacks
that architecture, however similar to us that entity is in its outward behavior. No such motivation suggests itself here.
Analogous considerations will likely trouble
most other attempts to exclude U.S. consciousness on broad architectural
grounds of this sort.
Dretske’s objection. Fred Dretske, in
correspondence, has suggested that the United States could not be conscious
because its representational states depend on the conscious states of
others. Such dependence, he says,
renders its representations conventional
rather than natural – and a conscious
entity must have natural representations.[21]
In earlier work, Dretske
(1995) highlights the implausibility of supposing that an object that has no
intrinsic representational functions can become conscious simply because
outside users impose representational functions upon it. We don’t make a mercury column conscious by
calling it a thermometer, nor do we make a machine conscious by calling it a
robot and interpreting its outputs as speech acts. The machine either is or is not conscious, it seems, independently of our intentions and
labels. A wide range of materialists, I
suspect, will and should accept that an entity cannot be conscious if all its
representations depend in this way on external agents. Focusing on such cases, Dretske’s
independency criterion seems appealing.
But the citizens and residents of the
United States are parts of the U.S. rather than external agents, and it’s not
clear that the dependency of consciousness on the intentions and purposes of internal agents is problematic in the
same way, if the internal agents’ behavior is properly integrated with the
whole. The internal and external cases,
at least, are sufficiently dissimilar that before accepting Dretske’s
principle in general form we should at least consider some potential
internal-agent cases. The Antarean antheads seem to be just
such a case, and I’ve suggested that the most natural materialist position is
to allow that they are conscious.
Furthermore, although Dretske’s criterion is
not exactly an anti-nesting principle in the sense of Section 2, it is subject
to the same concerns. In its broad form
it seems unmotivated, except by a desire to exclude the very cases in dispute,
and it brings new counterintuitive consequences in its train, such as loss of
consciousness upon inhaling Planck-scale people whose actions are smoothly
incorporated into one’s brain functions.
On Dretske’s proposed principle, as on the
anti-nesting principles of Section 2, entities that behave identically on a
large scale and have superficially similar evolutionary and developmental
histories might either have or lack consciousness depending on micro-level
differences that are seemingly unreportable (to
them), unintrospectible (to them), unrelated to what
they say about Proust, and thus, it seems natural to suppose, irrelevant.
Dretske
conceives his criterion as dividing “natural” representations from
“conventional” or artificial ones. Maybe
it is reasonable to insist that a conscious being have natural
representations. But from a telescopic
perspective national groups and their representational activities are eminently natural – as natural as
the structures and activities of groups of cells clustered into spatially
contiguous individual organisms. What
should matter on a broadly Dretskean approach, I’m
inclined to think, is that the representational functions emerge naturally from
within rather than being imposed artificially from outside, and that they are
properly ascribed to the whole entity rather than only to a subpart. Both Antarean
opinions about Shakespeare and the official U.S. position on Iran’s nuclear
program meet these criteria.
Dennett’s
objection. Daniel
Dennett, in correspondence, offers a pragmatic objection: To the extent the United
States is radically unlike individual human beings, it’s unhelpful to ascribe
consciousness to it. Its behavior is
impoverished compared to ours and its functional architecture radically unlike
our own. Ascribing consciousness to the
United States is not so much straightforwardly false, Dennett suggests, as it
is misleading, inviting the reader to too closely assimilate human architecture
and group architecture.
To this objection I respond, first, that
the United States is not behaviorally impoverished. It does lots of things, as described in
Sections 4 and 5 above – probably more than any individual human does. (In this way it differs from the aggregate of
the U.S., Germany, and South Africa, and maybe also from the aggregate of all
of humanity.) Second, to hang the
metaphysics of consciousness on fine details of architecture runs counter to
the spirit that admits the Sirians and Antareans to the realm of beings who would (hypothetically)
be conscious. Thus it risks collapse
into neurochauvinism (Section 7 below). And third, we can presumably dodge such
practical worries about leaping to assimilative inferences by being restrained
in our inferences. We can refrain from
assuming, for example, that when the U.S. is angry its anger is felt, phenomenologically, as anything like the anger of
individual human beings; we can even insist that “anger” is not a great word
and simply the best we can do with existing language. The U.S. can’t feel blood rush to its head;
it can’t feel tension in its arms; it can’t “see red”. It can muster its armies, denounce the
offender via spokespeople in Security Council meetings, and enforce an
embargo. What it feels like, if
anything, to enforce an embargo, defenders of U.S. consciousness can wisely
refrain from claiming to know.
Riffling through existing theories of
consciousness, we could try to find, or we could invent, some necessary
condition for consciousness that human beings meet, that the United States
fails to meet, and that sweeps in at least some of the more plausibly conscious
non-human entities. I would not object
to treating my argument as a challenge to which materialists might rise: Let’s find,
if we can, a plausible criterion that delivers this appealing conclusion!
Alternatively, some readers – perhaps
especially empirically-oriented readers – might suggest that my argument does
little other than display the bankruptcy of metaphysical speculation about
bizarre cases. How could we hope to build
any serious theory on science-fictional intuitions? I sympathize with this reaction too. Perhaps we should abandon any aspiration for
a truly universal metaphysics that would cover the whole range of bizarre
possibilities. The project seems so
ungrounded, so detached from our best sources of evidence about the world! But this reaction wouldn’t give us much
guidance about the question of U.S. consciousness, if we are suspicious enough
of common sense to think that our commonsensical reactions do not decisively
settle the question. Despite my
sympathies with skepticism about the metaphysics of bizarre cases, I want, and
I think it’s reasonable to want, at least a conditional assessment or best
guess about whether we are parts of a larger conscious entity. Is there a better way to try to reach such a
tentative assessment?
7. Three Ways Out.
Let’s briefly consider three more
conservative views about the distribution of consciousness in the universe, to
see if they can provide a suitable exit from the bizarre conclusion that the
United States is literally conscious.
Eliminativism. Maybe the United States isn’t conscious
because nobody is conscious – not
you, not me, not rabbits, not aliens.
Maybe “consciousness” is such a corrupt, broken concept, embedded in
such a radically false worldview, that we should discard it entirely, as we
discarded the concepts of demonic possession, the luminiferous
ether, and the fates.
In this essay, I have tried to use the
concept of consciousness in a plain
way, unadorned with dubious commitments like irreducibility, immateriality, and
infallible self-knowledge. Maybe I have
failed, but then I hope you will permit me to rephrase: Whatever it is in
virtue of which human beings and rabbits have appropriately unadorned
quasi-consciousness or consciousness*, the United States has that same thing.
The most visible philosophical eliminativists about terms from folk psychology still seem
to have room in their theories for consciousness, suitably stripped of dubious
commitments.[22] So if you tread this path, you’re going
farther than they. In fact, Paul Churchland
(1984/1988) says several things that seem, jointly, to commit him to accepting
the idea that cities or countries would be conscious (though he doesn’t to my
knowledge explicitly draw the conclusion).[23] Galen Strawson says
that denying the existence of conscious experience is “the strangest thing that
has ever happened in the whole history of human thought” (2006, p. 5). Strawson’s remark
underestimates, I suspect, the strangeness of religion; but still, radical eliminativism seems at least as bizarre as believing that
the United States is conscious.
Extreme
sparseness. Here’s
another way out for the materialist: Argue that consciousness is rare, so that
really only very specific types of systems possess it, and then argue that the
United States doesn’t meet the restrictive criteria. If the criteria are specifically neural, this position is neurochauvinism, which I will discuss shortly. Setting aside neurochauvinism,
the most commonly endorsed extreme sparseness view is one which language is required for
consciousness. Thus, dogs, wild apes,
and human infants aren’t conscious.
There’s nothing it’s like to be such beings, any more than there is
something it’s like (most people think) to be a diode or a fleck of dust. To a dog, all is dark inside, or rather, not
even dark. This view is both highly
counterintuitive and, I suspect, a gross overestimation of the gulf between us
and our nearest relatives.
However, it’s not clear that we get to
exclude U.S. consciousness by requiring language for consciousness, since the
United States does seemingly speak as a collective entity, as I’ve mentioned. It linguistically threatens and
self-represents, and these threats and self-representations influence the
linguistic and non-linguistic behavior of other nations. If the materialist is to deny U.S.
consciousness on grounds of a general commitment to the sparseness of
consciousness in the universe, then even more severe restrictions are required, or at least different ones. Perhaps phenomenal consciousness requires the
ability to self-report the existence of phenomenal consciousness? I’ll admit the United States doesn’t do that! But by this criterion even four-year-olds
might not be conscious.
Neurochauvinism. A third way out is to assume that
consciousness requires neurons –
neurons clumped together in the right way, communicating by ion channels and
all that, rather than by voice and gesture.
All the entities that we have actually met and that we normally regard
as conscious do have their neurons bundled in that way, and the 3 x 1019
neurons of the United States are not as a whole bundled that way.
Examples from Ned Block (1978/1991) and
John Searle (1980, 1984) lend intuitive support to this view. Suppose we arranged the people of China into
a giant communicative network resembling the functional network instantiated by
the human brain. It would be absurd,
Block says, to regard such an entity as conscious (though see Lycan 1981).
Similarly, Searle asserts that no arrangement of beer cans, wire, and
windmills, however cleverly arranged, could ever host a genuine stream of
conscious experience (though see Cuda 1985). According to Block and Searle, what these
entities are lacking isn’t a matter of large-scale functional structure
revealed in patterns of input-output relations.
Consciousness requires not that, or not only that; consciousness
requires human biology.
Or rather, consciousness, on this view,
requires something like human
biology. In what way
like? Here Block and Searle
aren’t very helpful. According to
Searle, “any system capable of causing consciousness must be capable of
duplicating the causal powers of the brain” (1992, p. 92). In principle, Searle suggests, this could be
achieved by “altogether different” physical mechanisms. But what mechanisms could do this and what
mechanisms could not, Searle makes no attempt to adjudicate, other than by
excluding certain systems, like beer-can systems, as plainly the wrong sort of
thing. Instead, Searle gestures
hopefully at future science.
The reason for not strictly insisting on
neurons, I suspect, is this: If we’re playing the common sense game – that is,
if bizarreness by the standards of current common sense is our reason for
excluding beer-can systems and organized groups of people – then we’re going to
have to allow the possibility, at least in principle, of conscious beings from
other planets who operate other than by neural systems like our own. By whatever commonsense or intuitive
standards we judge beer-can systems nonconscious, by
those very same standards, it seems, we would judge hypothetical Martians, with
different internal biology but intelligent-seeming outward behavior, to be
conscious.
From a cosmological perspective it would
be strange to suppose that of all the possible beings in the universe that are
capable of sophisticated, self-preserving, goal-directed environmental
responsiveness, beings that could presumably be (and in a vast enough universe
presumably actually are) constructed in myriad strange and diverse ways,
somehow only we with our neurons have genuine conscious experience, and all
else are mere automata there is nothing it is like anything to be. Contrary to the “Copernican Principle” of
cosmological method,[24]
this view would suggest that we, as the sole possessors of consciousness, are
in a uniquely favored position in the universe.
How lucky we are! (The other
beings, I suppose, only say they’re
lucky, or only emit noises that we would mistakenly regard as having that
semantic content.) For this reason, it
seems not only unintuitive but also scientifically unjustified to suppose that
conscious experience requires Earthly biology.
It would be like supposing that life requires Earthly nucleotides.
If they’re to avoid un-Copernican neuro-fetishism, the question must become, for Block and
Searle, what feature of neurons,
possibly also possessed by non-neural systems, gives rise to
consciousness? In other words, we are
back with the question of Section 5 – what is so special about brains? – and
the only well-developed answers on the near horizon seem to involve appeals to
the sorts of features that the United States has, features like massively
complex informational integration, functionally directed self-monitoring, and a
long-standing history of sophisticated environmental responsiveness.
8. Conclusion.
In sum, the argument is this. There seems to be no principled reason to
deny entityhood, or entityhood-enough,
to spatially distributed beings if they are well enough integrated in other
ways. By this criterion, the United
States is at least a candidate for
the literal possession of real psychological states, including
consciousness. If we’re willing to
entertain this perspective, the question then becomes whether it meets
plausible materialistic criteria for consciousness. My suggestion is that if those criteria are
liberal enough to include both small mammals and
highly intelligent aliens, then the United States probably does meet those
criteria. Although that conclusion seems
absurdly bizarre, even a passing glance at contemporary physics and metaphysics
suggests that common sense is no sure guide to fundamental reality.
Large things are hard to see properly
when you’re in their midst. The
homunculi in your head, the tourist in Leibniz’s mill, they don’t see
consciousness either.[25] Too vivid an appreciation of the local mechanisms
overwhelms their view. The space between
us is an airy synapse.
If the United States is conscious, is
Exxon-Mobil? Is an aircraft carrier?[26] Is the seven dwarfs
of Snow White? And if such entities are conscious, do they
have rights? Is dissolution murder? I don’t know.
The bizarrenesses multiply, and I worry about
the moral implications.
Neither do I know whether I have
provided grounds for believing that the United States is conscious, or instead
a challenge to existing materialist theories of consciousness, or instead
reasons to be wary of ambitions toward a universal metaphysics of mind. Whoops, I hear something knocking on my
office door....[27]
References:
Allen,
Colin (1995/2010). Animal
consciousness. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2011 edition).
Arico,
Adam (2010). Folk
psychology, consciousness, and context effects. Review
of Philosophy and Psychology, 1, 371-393.
Averroës
(Ibn Rushd) (12th
c./2009). Long commentary on the De
Anima of Aristotle, trans. R.C. Taylor. New Haven: Yale.
Baars,
Bernard J. (1988). A cognitive theory of consciousness. Cambridge: Cambridge.
Balduzzi,
David, and Giulio Tononi
(2009). Qualia: The geometry of integrated information. PLoS Computational
Biology, 5: 8.
Barnett,
David (2008). The
simplicity intuition and its hidden influence on philosophy of mind. Noûs, 42, 308-335.
Barnett,
David (2010). You are simple. In The waning of
materialism, ed. R.C. Koons and G. Bealer. Oxford:
Oxford.
Beisbart,
Claus, and Tobias Jung (2006). Privileged, typical, or not
even that? Our
place in the world according to the Copernican and Cosmological Principles. Journal
for General Philosophy of Science, 37, 225-256.
Bettencourt,
B. Ann, Marilynn B. Brewer, Marian Rogers Croak, and Normal Miller (1992). Cooperation and the reduction of intergroup
bias: The role of reward structure and social orientation. Journal
of Experimental Social Psychology, 28, 301-319.
Block,
Ned (1978/1991). Troubles
with functionalism. In The nature of mind,
ed. D.M. Rosenthal. Oxford:
Oxford..
Block,
Ned (2002). The harder
problem of consciousness. Journal of Philosophy, 99, 391-425.
Bondi,
Herman (1952/1968). Cosmology, 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge.
Bratman,
Michael (1999). Faces of intention. Cambridge: Cambridge.
Burge,
Tyler (1979). Individualism
and the mental. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 4,
73-122.
Campbell,
Donald T. (1958). Common
fate, similarity, and other indices of the status of aggregates of persons as
social entities. Behavioral Science, 3, 14-25.
Carey,
Susan (2009). The origin of concepts. Oxford: Oxford.
Carruthers,
Peter (1996). Language, thought and consciousness. Cambridge: Cambridge.
Carruthers,
Peter (1998). Animal
subjectivity. Psyche, 4: 3.
Carruthers,
Peter (2001/2011). Higher-order
theories of consciousness. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2011 edition).
Chomsky,
Noam (2009). The mysteries of nature:
How deeply hidden? Journal of Philosophy, 106, 167-200.
Churchland,
Patricia S. (1983). Consciousness: The
transmutation of a concept. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 64, 80-95.
Churchland,
Patricia S. (2002). Brain-wise. Cambridge, MA: MIT.
Churchland,
Paul M. (1981). Eliminative
materialism and the propositional attitudes. Journal
of Philosophy, 78, 67-90.
Churchland,
Paul M. (1984/1988). Matter and consciousness, rev. ed. Cambridge,
MA: MIT.
Churchland,
Paul M. (1984/1988). Matter and consciousness, rev. ed. Cambridge,
MA: MIT.
Clark,
Andy (2009). Spreading the joy? Why the machinery of consciousness is
(probably) still in the head. Mind, 118, 963-993.
Clark,
Austen (1994). Beliefs and desires
incorporated. Journal of Philosophy, 91, 404-425.
Crick,
Francis (1994). The astonishing hypothesis. New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons.
Cuda,
Tom (1985). Against
neural chauvinism. Philosophical Studies, 48, 111-127.
Davidson,
Donald (1987). Knowing one’s own mind. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical
Association, 61, 441–58.
Dennett,
Daniel C. (1991). Consciousness explained.
Boston: Little, Brown, and Company.
Dennett,
Daniel C. (1996). Kinds of minds. New York: BasicBooks.
Dennett,
Daniel C. (1998). Brainchildren. Cambridge, MA: MIT.
Dennett,
Daniel C. (2005). Sweet dreams. Cambridge, MA:
MIT.
Descartes, René (1649/1991). Letter to More, 5 Feb. 1649. In The philosophical writings of Descartes, vol. 3, ed. J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, D. Murdoch, and A. Kenny. Cambridge: Cambridge.
Dretske,
Fred (1988). Explaining behavior. Cambridge, MA: MIT.
Dretske,
Fred (1995). Naturalizing the mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT.
Edelman, Shimon (2008). Computing the mind. Oxford: Oxford.
Egan, Greg (1992). Closer. Eidelon, vol. 8. Available
at http://www.eidolon.net/old_site/issue_09/09_closr.htm .
Elder,
Crawford (2011). Familiar objects and their
shadows. Cambridge:
Cambridge.
Espinas,
Alfred (1877/1924). Des sociétés animales,
3rd ed.
Paris: Félix Alcan.
Fodor, Jerry A. (1968). The appeal to tacit
knowledge in psychological explanation.
Journal of Philosophy, 65,
627-640.
Frankish, Keith (2012). Quining diet qualia. Consciousness
and Cognition, 21, 667-676.
Gendler, Tamar Szabó (2008a). Alief and belief. Journal
of Philosophy, 105, 634–663.
Gendler, Tamar Szabó (2008b). Alief in action, and reaction.
Mind & Language, 23,
552–585.
Gilbert,
Margaret (1989). On social facts. Princeton, NJ: Princeton.
Godfrey-Smith,
Peter (2009). Darwinian populations and natural selection. Oxford: Oxford.
Godfrey-Smith,
Peter (forthcoming). Darwinian
individuals. In
From groups to individuals, ed. F.
Bouchard and P. Huneman. Cambridge, MA: MIT.
Gopnik,
Alison, and Eric Schwitzgebel (1998). Whose concepts are they, anyway? The role of philosophical
intuition in empirical psychology.
In Rethinking
intuition, ed. M.R. DePaul and W. Ramsey. Lanham: Rowman and
Littlefield.
Greene, Brian (2011). The hidden reality.
New York: Vintage.
Haslanger, Sally (2008). Changing the ideology and culture of philosophy: Not by reason
(alone). Hypatia,
23, 210-22.
Hilbert,
Martin, and Priscila López
(2011). The world’s
technological capacity to store, communicate, and
compute information. Science, 332, 60-65.
Hill,
Christopher S. (1991). Sensations. Cambridge: Cambridge.
Hill,
Christopher S. (2009). Consciousness. Cambridge: Cambridge.
Huebner,
Bryce (forthcoming). Macrocognition. Oxford:
Oxford
Huebner,
Bryce, Michael Bruno, and Hagop Sarkissian
(2010). What does
the nation of China think about phenomenal states? Review
of Philosophy and Psychology, 1, 225-243.
Hume,
David (1740/1978). A treatise of human nature, ed. L.A.
Selby-Bigge and P.H. Nidditch. Oxford: Oxford.
Hurley,
Susan (1998). Consciousness in action. Cambridge, MA: Harvard.
Hutchins,
Edwin (1995). Cognition in the wild. Cambridge, MA: MIT.
Kant,
Immanuel (1781/1787/1998). Critique of pure reason,
ed. and trans. P. Guyer and A.W. Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge.
Knobe,
Joshua, and Jesse Prinz (2008). Intuitions about consciousness: Experimental
studies. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 7, 67-83.
Koch,
Christof (2012).
Consciousness: Confessions of a
romantic reductionist. Cambridge,
MA: MIT.
Korman,
Daniel (2011). Ordinary
objects. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter
2011 edition).
Kornblith,
Hilary (1998). The role of intuition in
philosophical inquiry: An account with no unnatural ingredients. In Rethinking intuition, ed. M.R. DePaul and W. Ramsey. Lanham: Rowman and
Littlefield.
Kurzweil,
Ray (2005). The singularity is near. New
York: Penguin.
Ladyman,
James, and Don Ross (2007). Every thing must go. Oxford: Oxford.
Leibniz,
G.W. (1714/1989). The principles of philosophy, or, the monadology. In Philosophical Essays, ed. and trans. R. Ariew
and D. Garber. Indianapolis: Hackett.
Lewis.
David K. (1980). Mad
pain and Martian pain. In Readings in philosophy of
psychology, ed. N. Block. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard.
List,
Christian, and Philip Pettit (2011). Group agency. Oxford:
Oxford.
Lycan,
William G. (1981). Form, function, and
feel. Journal of Philosophy, 78, 24-50.
Madden,
Rory (forthcoming). The
naive topology of the conscious subject.
Noûs.
Mandik,
Pete, and Josh Weisberg (2008). Type Q materialism. In Naturalism, reference, and ontology, ed. C.B. Wrenn. New York: Peter Lang.
Maynard
Smith, John, and Eors Szathmáry
(1995). The major transitions in
evolution. Oxford: Oxford.
McDougall,
William (1920). The group mind. New York:
Putnam.
McLaughlin,
Brian (2007). Type
materialism for phenomenal consciousness. In The Blackwell companion to consciousness, ed. M. Velmans and S. Schneider. Malden, MA: Blackwell.
Metzinger,
Thomas (2003). Being no one. Cambridge, MA: MIT.
Millikan,
Ruth Garrett (1984). Language, thought, and other biological
categories. Cambridge, MA:
MIT.
Millikan,
Ruth Garrett (2010). On knowing the
meaning: With a coda on Swampman. Mind,
119, 43-81.
Montero,
Barbara (1999). The body problem. Noûs, 33, 183-200.
Moravec,
Hans (1997). When will computer hardware
match the human brain? Available at
http://www.transhumanist.com/volume1/moravec.htm (accessed June 1, 2012).
Noë,
Alva (2004). Action in perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT.
Parfit,
Derek (1984). Reasons and persons. Oxford: Oxford.
Petty, Richard E., Russell H. Fazio, and Pablo Briñol, eds. (2009). Attitudes:
Insights from the new implicit measures. New York: Taylor and Francis.
Phelan, Mark, Adam Arico, and Shaun
Nichols (forthcoming). Thinking things and feeling
things: On an alleged discontinuity in folk metaphysics of mind.
Polger,
Thomas W. (2004). Natural minds. Cambridge, MA: MIT.
Putnam, Hilary (1965). Psychological predicates. In Art, mind, and religion, ed. W.H. Capitan & D.D. Merrill. Liverpool: University of Pittsburgh Press / C.
Tinling.
Putnam,
Hilary (1975). Mind, language and reality. London: Cambridge.
Rockwell,
Teed (2005). Neither brain nor
ghost. Cambridge, MA: MIT.
Rupert, R. (2005). Minding one’s own cognitive system:
When is a group of minds a single cognitive unit? Episteme, 1, 177-88.
Ryle,
Gilbert (1949). The concept of mind. New York: Barnes & Noble.
Saul,
Jennifer (forthcoming). Implicit bias, stereotype threat and women in philosophy. In Women in philosophy, ed. F. Jenkins and K. Hutichson.
Schäffle,
Albert E. F. (1896). Bau und Leben des socialen
Körpers, 2nd ed. Tübingen: Laupp’schen.
Scholl,
Brian (2007). Object persistence in
philosophy and psychology. Mind & Language, 22, 563-591.
Schwitzgebel,
Eric (2010). Acting
contrary to our professed beliefs, or the gulf between occurrent
judgment and dispositional belief.
Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 91, 531-553.
Schwitzgebel,
Eric (2012a). Group minds on Ringworld. Blog post at The Splintered Mind (http://schwitzsplinters.blogspot.com),
October 24, 2012.
Schwitzgebel,
Eric (2012b). Why Dennett should think
that the United States is conscious. Blog post at The Splintered Mind
(http://schwitzsplinters.blogspot.com), Feb. 9, 2012.
Schwitzgebel,
Eric (2012c). Why Dretske
should think that the United States is conscious. Blog post at The Splintered
Mind (http://schwitzsplinters.blogspot.com), Feb. 17, 2012.
Schwitzgebel,
Eric (2012d). Why Humphrey should think
that the United States is conscious. Blog post at The Splintered Mind
(http://schwitzsplinters.blogspot.com), Mar. 8, 2012.
Schwitzgebel,
Eric (2012e). Why Tononi
should think that the United States is conscious. Blog post at The Splintered
Mind (http://schwitzsplinters.blogspot.com), Mar. 23, 2012.
Schwitzgebel,
Eric (2012f). Why Tononi
should allow that conscious entities can have conscious parts. Blog post at The Splintered
Mind (http://schwitzsplinters.blogspot.com), June 6, 2012.
Schwitzgebel,
Eric (in draft). The crazyist metaphysics of mind. Available at http://faculty.ucr.edu/~eschwitz
Searle,
John (1980). Minds,
brains, and programs. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3,
417-457.
Searle,
John (1984). Minds, brains, and science. Cambridge, MA: Harvard.
Searle,
John (1992). The rediscovery of the mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT.
Searle,
John (2010). Making the social world. Oxford: Oxford.
Sober,
Elliott, and David Sloan Wilson (1998). Unto others. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard.
Spelke,
Elizabeth S., Karen Breinlinger, Janet Macomber, and Kristen Jacobson (1992). Origins of knowledge. Psychological
Review, 99, 605-632.
Stich,
Stephen (1983). From folk psychology to
cognitive science. Cambridge,
MA: MIT.
Stich,
Stephen (2009).
Five answers. In
Mind and consciousness, ed. S. Grim.
Automatic Press.
Stock,
Gregory (1993). Metaman. Toronto: Doubleday Canada.
Stoljar,
Daniel (2010). Physicalism. Oxford: Routledge.
Strawson,
Galen (2006). Consciousness and its place in nature. Exeter: Imprint Academic.
Strawson,
P.F. (1959). Individuals. London: Methuen.
Sytsma,
Justin M., and Edouard Machery
(2010). Two conceptions of subjective experience. Philosophical Studies, 151, 299-327.
Teilhard
de Chardin, Pierre (1955/1965). The phenomenon of man, rev. English ed., trans. B. Wall. New York: Harper & Row.
Tononi,
Giulio (2004).
An information integration theory of consciousness. BMC Neuroscience, 5: 42.
Tononi,
Giulio (2008).
Consciousness as integrated information: A provisional manifesto. Biological
Bulletin, 215, 216-242.
Tononi,
Giulio (2010).
Information integration: Its relevance to brain function and consciousness. Archives Italiennes de Biologie,
148, 299-322.
Tononi,
Giulio (2012).
Phi. New York: Pantheon.
Tononi,
Giulio (forthcoming).
The integrated information theory of consciousness: An updated
account. Archives Italiennes
de Biologie.
Tuomela,
Raimo (2007). The philosophy of sociality. Oxford: Oxford.
Turing,
A.M. (1950). Computing
machinery and intelligence. Mind, 59, 433-460.
Vinge,
Vernor (1992).
A fire upon the
deep. New York: Tor.
Vinge,
Vernor (2011).
Children of the
sky. New York: Tor.
Wason,
P.C. (1968). Reasoning
about a rule. Quarterly Journal of Experimental
Psychology, 20, 273-281.
Wilson,
Robert A. (2004). Boundaries of the mind. Cambridge: Cambridge.
Wilson,
Robert A. (2005). Genes and the agents of life. Cambridge: Cambridge.
Wittenbrink, Bernd, and Norbert Schwarz, eds. (2007). Implicit
measures of attitudes. New York:
Guilford.
Wundt,
Wilhelm (1897/1897). Outlines of psychology, trans. C. H.
Judd. Leipzig: Wilhelm Engelmann.
[1] For
purposes of this essay, I’m going to assume that we know, at least roughly,
what “material stuff” is. I recognize
that this assumption might be problematic.
Discussions include Montero 1999; Chomsky 2009; Stoljar
2010.
[2] The
empirical literature on folk opinion about group consciousness is more equivocal
than I would have thought, however. See Knobe and Prinz 2008; Sytsma and Machery 2009; Arico 2010; Huebner, Bruno, and Sarkissian
2010; Phelan, Arico, and Nichols forthcoming.
Few scholars have clearly endorsed the
possibility of literal group consciousness.
On group minds without literal consciousness see McDougall 1920; Wilson
2004; and the recent literature on collective intentionality (e.g., Gilbert
1989; Clark 1994; Bratman 1999; Rupert 2005; Tuomela 2007; Searle 2010; List and Pettit 2011; Huebner
forthcoming).
For more radical views of group minds
see Espinas 1877/1924; Schäffle
1875/1896; maybe Wundt 1897/1897; maybe Strawson 1959
(none of whom were materialists).
Perhaps the best developed group consciousness view – with some
affinities to the present view, though again not materialist – is that of Tielhard de Chardin
1955/1965. See also Lewis & Viharo’s “Google Consciousness”, TEDxCardiff
(June 9, 2011); Vernor Vinge’s
science fiction portrayal of group minds in Vinge
1992, 2011; Averroës (Ibn Rushd) on the active intellect, 12th c./2009; Edelman
2008, p. 432; Koch 2012, p. 131-134.
[3] I
develop this idea farther in Schwitzgebel in draft. Some others who doubt common sense as a guide
to metaphysics are Churchland 1981; Stich 1983; Gopnik and
Schwitzgebel 1998; Kornblith 1998; Dennett 2005; Ladyman and Ross 2007; Mandik and
Weisberg 2008. Hume 1740/1978 and Kant
1781/1787/1998 are also interesting on this issue, of course.
[5] See,
for example, the essays collected in Wittenbrink and Schwarz, eds., 2007; Petty, Fazio, and Briñol, eds., 2009.
Philosophical discussions include Gendler
2008a-b; Haslanger 2008; Schwitzgebel 2010; Saul
forthcoming.
[6] Especially if the entity’s parts move on diverse trajectories. See, for example, Campbell
1958; Spelke, Brelinger, Macomber, and Jacobson 1992; Scholl 2007; Carey 2009. See Barnett 2008 and Madden forthcoming for
philosophical arguments that we do not intuitively attribute consciousness to
scattered objects.
[10] See
also Barnett 2008, 2010; Madden 2012; and for comparison Godfrey-Smith
forthcoming on the “exclusion principle” regarding biological organisms. Barnett, like Putnam, seems to rely simply on
an intuitive sense of absurdity (2010, p. 162).
In an earlier work, Tononi (2010, note 9)
discusses an anti-nesting principle without endorsing it. There he states that such a principle is “in
line with the intuitions that each of us has a single, sharply demarcated
consciousness”. In his more recent
article, Tononi does not repeat his appeal to that
intuition.
[11] In
conversation, Tononi has resisted this
suggestion. However, it remains unclear
to me what might justify his resistance on this point, especially given his
principle that spatial and temporal grain are not intrinsically meaningful but
rather should be chosen to maximize the measure of integrated information. (I choose a temporal grain of one day and a
spatial grain of one node per voter.)
[12] For a review of
“type materialism” see McLaughlin 2007.
For more detail how some of the options described in this paragraph
might play out, see Lewis 1980; Bechtel and Mundale
1999; Polger 2004; Hill 2009. Block 2002 illustrates the skeptical
consequences of embracing type identity without committing to some possibility
of broadly this sort.
[14] E.g., Hurley 1998; Noë 2004; Wilson 2004;
Rockwell 2005.
[15] E.g., Putnam 1975; Burge 1979; Millikan 1984; Davidson 1987; Dretske 1988, 1995; Wilson 2004.
[16] See also Moravec 1997; Kurzweil 2005;
Hilbert and López 2011.
[17] See e.g.,
Davidson 1987; Dretske 1995; Millikan 2010.
[18] Two notable
exceptions are Robert A. Wilson (2004) and Bryce Huebner (forthcoming). Huebner seems open to the possibility of
group consciousness while refraining from endorsing it. Wilson I am inclined to read as rejecting
group consciousness on the grounds that it has been advocated only sparsely and
confusedly, with no advocate meeting a reasonable burden of proof. Edelman (2008) and Koch (2012) make passing
but favorable remarks about group consciousness, at least hypothetically. Tononi and Putnam I
discuss in Section 2.
[19] For a review of
higher-order theories, see Carruthers 2001/2011.
[20] The theories I
chose were Dretske’s, Dennett’s, Humphrey’s, and Tononi’s. You can
see some of my preliminary efforts in blog posts Schwitzgebel 2012b-f (compare
also Koch’s sympathetic 2012 treatment of Tononi). On the most natural interpretations of these
four test-case views, I thought that readers sympathetic with any of these
authors’ general approaches ought to accept that the United States is
conscious. And I confess I still do
think that, despite protests from Dretske, Dennett,
Humphrey, and Tononi themselves in personal
communication. See the comments section
of Schwitzgebel 2012d for Humphrey’s reaction, the remainder of the present
section for Dretske and Dennett, and Section 2 for Tononi.
[21] In his 1995
book, Dretske says that a representational is natural
if it is not “derived from the intentions and purposes of its designers,
builders, and users” (p. 7) rather than the more general criterion, above, of
independency from “others”. In light of
our correspondence on group consciousness, he says that he has modified this
aspect of his view.
[22] P.M. Churchland 1984/1988; P.S. Churchland 2002; Stich 2009. Contrast skepticism about
loaded versions of “consciousness” or “qualia” in
P.S. Churchland 1983; Dennett 1991; Frankish 2012.
[23] Churchland characterizes as a living being “any semiclosed system that exploits the order it already
possesses, and the energy flux through it, in such a way as to maintain and/or
increase its internal order” (1984/1988, p. 173). By this definition, Churchland
suggests, beehives, cities, and the entire biosphere
all qualify as living beings (ibid.).
Consciousness and intelligence, Churchland
further suggests, are simply sophistications of this basic pattern – cases in
which the semiclosed system exploits energy to
increase the information it contains, including information about its own
internal states and processes (1984/1988, p. 173 and 178).
[24] Bondi 1952/1968;
Beisbart and Jung 2006.
[25] On the
homunculi, see e.g., Fodor 1968. Leibniz
imagines entering into an enlarged brain as into a mill in his 1714/1989.
[26] Hutchins 1995
vividly portrays distributed cognition in a military vessel. I don’t know whether he would extend his
conclusions to phenomenal consciousness, however.
[27] For helpful
discussion of these issues in the course of writing, thanks to Rachel Achs, Santiago Arango, Scott Bakker, Zachary Barnett, Mark
Biswas, Ned Block, David Daedalus, Dan Dennett, Fred Dretske, Louie Favela, Kirk Gable, Peter Godfrey-Smith, Chris
Hill, Linus Huang, Nick Humphrey, Enoch Lambert, Bill Lycan,
Pete Mandik, Tori McGeer, Luke Roelofs, Giulio Tononi, Vernor Vinge, and Rob Wilson; to
audiences at University of Cincinnati, Princeton University, Tufts University,
University of Basque Country, and Bob Richardson’s seminar on extended
cognition; and to the many readers who posted comments on relevant posts on my
blog, The Splintered Mind. My wife
Pauline sensibly worries that I am too passionate in defending the rights of antheads who, she says, don’t even really exist. My thirteen-year-old son Davy, however,
thinks that for the first time in my career I’m now actually writing about
something interesting. The seven dwarfs example is his.