Jerks: A Field Guide
Eric
Schwitzgebel
Picture the
world through the eyes of the jerk. The line of people in post office is a mass
of unimportant fools; it’s a felt injustice that you must wait while they
bumble with their requests. The flight attendant is not a potentially
interesting person with her own cares and struggles but instead the most
available face of a corporation that stupidly insists you shut your phone.
Custodians and secretaries are lazy complainers who rightly get the scut work. The person who disagrees with you at the staff
meeting is an idiot to be shot down. Entering a subway is an exercise in
nudging past the dumb schmoes.
We need a
theory of jerks. We need such a theory because, first, it can help us achieve a
calm, clinical understanding when confronting such a creature in the wild.
Imagine the nature-documentary voice-over: ‘Here we see the jerk in his natural
environment. Notice how he subtly adjusts his dominance display to the Italian
restaurant situation….’ And second – well, I don’t want to say what the second
reason is quite yet.
As it
happens, I do have such a theory. But before we get into it, I should clarify
some terminology. The word ‘jerk’ can refer to two different types of person (I
set aside sexual uses of the term, as well as more purely physical senses). The
older use of ‘jerk’ designates a kind of chump or an ignorant fool, though not
a morally odious one. When Weird Al Yankovic sang, in
2006, ‘I sued Fruit of the Loom ’cause when I wear their tightie-whities on my head I look like a jerk’, or when, on
March 1, 1959, Willard Temple wrote in the Los
Angeles Times: ‘He could have married the campus queen… Instead the poor
jerk fell for a snub-nosed, skinny little broad’, it’s clear it's the chump
they have in mind. The jerk-as-fool usage seems to have begun as a derisive
reference to the unsophisticated people of a ‘jerkwater town’: that is, a town
not rating a full-scale train station, requiring the boilerman
to pull on a chain to water his engine. The term expresses the travelling
troupe’s disdain. Over time, however, ‘jerk’ shifted from being primarily a
class-based insult to its second, now dominant sense as a term of moral
condemnation. Such linguistic drift from class-based contempt to moral
deprecation is a common pattern across languages, as observed by Nietzsche in On the Genealogy of Morality. (In
English, consider ‘rude’, ‘villain’, ‘ignoble’.) And it is the immoral jerk who concerns me here.
Why, you may
be wondering, should a philosopher make it his business to analyse
colloquial terms of abuse? Doesn’t Urban Dictionary cover that kind of thing
quite adequately? Shouldn’t I confine myself to truth, or beauty, or knowledge,
or why there is something rather than nothing (Sidney Morgenbesser’s
answer: ‘if there was nothing, still you’d complain’)? I am, in fact,
interested in all those topics. And yet I suspect there’s a folk wisdom in the
term ‘jerk’ that points toward something morally important. I want to extract
that morally important thing, to isolate the core phenomenon towards which I
think the word is groping. Precedents for this type of work include Harry
Frankfurt on bullshit and, closer to my target, Aaron James on the asshole. Our
taste in vulgarity reveals our values..
I submit
that the unifying core, the essence of jerkitude in the moral sense, is this: the jerk culpably fails to appreciate the
perspectives of others around him, treating them as tools to be manipulated or
idiots to be dealt with rather than as moral and epistemic peers. This
failure has both an intellectual dimension and an emotional dimension, and it
has these two dimensions on both side of the relationship. The jerk himself is
both intellectually and emotionally defective, and what he defectively fails to
appreciate is both the intellectual and emotional perspectives of the people
around him. He can’t appreciate how he might be wrong and others right about
some matter of fact; and what other people want or value doesn’t register as of
interest to him, except derivatively upon his own interests. The bumpkin
ignorance captured in the earlier use of ‘jerk’ has changed into a type of
moral ignorance.
Some related
traits are already well known in psychology and philosophy – the ‘dark triad’
of Machiavellianism, narcissism, and psychopathy, and Aaron James’s conception
of the asshole, already mentioned. But my conception of the jerk differs from
all of these. The asshole, James says, is someone who allows himself to enjoy
special advantages out of an entrenched sense of entitlement. That is one
important dimension of jerkitude, but not the whole story. The callous
psychopath, though cousin to the jerk, has an impulsivity and love of risk-taking
that need be no part of the jerk’s character. Neither does the jerk have to be
as thoroughly self-involved as the narcissist or as self-consciously cynical as
the Machiavellian, though narcissism and Machiavellianism are common enough jerkish attributes. My conception of the ‘jerk’ also has a
conceptual unity that is, I think, both theoretically appealing in the abstract
and fruitful in helping explain some of the peculiar features of this type of
animal, as we will see.
The opposite
of the jerk is the sweetheart. The
sweetheart sees others around him, even strangers, as individually distinctive
people with valuable perspectives, whose desires and opinions and interests and
goals are worthy of attention and respect. The sweetheart yields his place in
line to the hurried shopper, stops to help the person who dropped her papers,
calls an acquaintance with an embarrassed apology
after having been unintentionally rude. In a debate, the sweetheart sees how he
might be wrong and the other person right.
The moral
and emotional failure of the jerk is obvious. The intellectual failure is, too:
no one is as right about everything as the jerk thinks he is. He would learn by
listening. And one of the things he might learn by listening is the true scope
of his jerkitude – a fact about which, as I will explain shortly, the all-out
jerk is inevitably ignorant. Which brings me to the other great benefit of a
theory of jerks: it might help you figure out if you yourself are one.
*
Some clarifications and caveats.
First, no
one is a perfect jerk or a perfect sweetheart. Human
behaviour – of
course! – varies hugely with context. Different situations (sales-team
meetings, travelling in close quarters) might bring out the jerk in some and the
sweetie in others.
Second, the
jerk is someone who culpably fails to
appreciate the perspectives of others around him. Young children and people
with severe mental disabilities aren’t capable of appreciating others’
perspectives, so they can’t be blamed for their failure and aren’t jerks. Also,
not all perspectives deserve equal treatment. Failure to appreciate the outlook
of a neo-Nazi, for example, is not sign of jerkitude – though the true
sweetheart might bend over backwards to try.
Third, I’ve
called the jerk ‘he’, for reasons you might guess. But then it seems too
gendered to call the sweetheart ‘she’, so I’ve made the sweetheart a ‘he’ too.
I said that
my theory might help us to tell whether we, ourselves, are jerks. But in fact
this turns out to be a peculiarly difficult question. The psychologist Simine
Vazire has argued that we tend to know our own characteristics quite well when
the relevant traits are evaluatively neutral and straightforwardly
observable, and badly when they are loaded with value judgments and not
straightforwardly observable. If you ask someone how talkative she is, or
whether she is relatively high-strung or relatively mellow, and then you ask
her friends to rate her along the same dimensions, the self-rating and the peer
ratings usually correlate quite well – and both sets of ratings also tend to
line up with psychologists’ best attempts to measure such traits objectively.
Why? Presumably because it’s more or less fine to be talkative and more or less
fine to be quiet, OK to be a bouncing bunny and OK instead to keep it low-key, and such traits are hard to miss in any case. But
few of us want to be inflexible, stupid, unfair or low in creativity. And if
you don’t want to see yourself that way, it’s easy enough to dismiss the signs.
Such characteristics are, after all, connected to outward behaviour
in somewhat complicated ways; we can always cling to the idea that we have been
misunderstood. Thus we overlook our own faults.
With Vazire’s model of self-knowledge in mind, I conjecture a
correlation of approximately zero between how one would rate oneself in
relative jerkitude and one’s actual true jerkitude. The term is morally loaded,
and rationalisation is so tempting and easy! Why did
you just treat that cashier so harshly? Well, she deserved it – and anyway,
I’ve been having a rough day. Why did you just cut into that line of cars at
the last minute, not waiting your turn to exit? Well, that’s just good tactical
driving – and anyway, I’m in a hurry! Why did you seem to relish failing that
student for submitting her essay an hour late? Well, the rules were clearly
stated; it’s only fair to the students who worked hard to submit their essays
on time – and that was a grimace not a smile.
Since the
most effective way to learn about defects in one’s character is to listen to
frank feedback from people whose opinions you respect, the jerk faces special obstacles
on the road to self-knowledge, beyond even what Vazire’s
model would lead us to expect. By definition, he fails to respect the
perspectives of others around him. He’s much more likely to dismiss critics as
fools – or as themselves jerks – than to take the
criticism to heart.
Still, it’s
entirely possible for a picture-perfect jerk to acknowledge, in a superficial way, that he is a jerk. ‘So
what, yeah, I’m a jerk’, he might say. Provided this label carries no real
sting of self-disapprobation, the jerk’s moral self-ignorance remains. Part of
what it is to fail to appreciate the perspectives of others is to fail to see
your jerkishly dismissive attitude toward their ideas
and concerns as inappropriate.
Ironically,
it is the sweetheart who worries that he has just behaved inappropriately, that
he might have acted too jerkishly, and who feels
driven to make amends. Such distress is impossible if you don’t take others’
perspectives seriously into account. Indeed, the distress itself constitutes a
deviation (in this one respect at least) from pure jerkitude: worrying about
whether it might be so helps to make it less so. Then again, if you take
comfort in that fact and cease worrying, you have undermined the very basis of
your comfort.
*
All normal
jerks distribute their jerkishness mostly down the social hierarchy, and to
anonymous strangers. Waitresses, students, clerks, strangers on the road – these
are the unfortunates who bear the brunt of it. With a modicum of self-control,
the jerk, though he implicitly or explicitly regards himself as more important
than most of the people around him, recognises that
the perspectives of those above him in the hierarchy also deserve some
consideration. Often, indeed, he feels sincere respect for his higher-ups. Perhaps
respectful feelings are too deeply written in our natures to disappear
entirely. Perhaps the jerk retains a vestigial kind of concern specifically for
those whom it would benefit him, directly or indirectly, to win over. He is at
least concerned enough about their opinion of him to display tactical respect
while in their field of view. However it comes about, the classic jerk kisses
up and kicks down. The company CEO rarely knows who the jerks are, though it’s
no great mystery among the secretaries.
Because the
jerk tends to disregard the perspectives of those below him in the hierarchy,
he often has little idea how he appears to them. This leads to hypocrisies. He
might rage against the smallest typo in a student’s or secretary’s document
while producing a torrent of errors himself; it just wouldn’t occur to him to
apply the same standards to himself. He might insist on promptness while always
running late. He might freely reprimand other people, expecting them to take it
with good grace, while any complaints directed against him earn his eternal
enmity. Such failures of parity typify the jerk’s moral shortsightedness,
flowing naturally from his disregard of others’ perspectives. These hypocrisies
are immediately obvious if one genuinely imagines oneself in a subordinate’s
shoes for anything other than selfish and self-rationalising
ends, but this is exactly what the jerk habitually fails to do.
Embarrassment,
too, becomes practically impossible for the jerk, at least in front of his
underlings. Embarrassment requires us to imagine being viewed negatively by
people whose perspectives we care about. As the circle of people whom the jerk
is willing to regard as true peers and superiors shrinks, so does his capacity
for shame – and with it a crucial entry point for moral self-knowledge.
As one
climbs the social hierarchy it is also easier to become a jerk. Here’s a characteristically jerkish
thought: ‘I’m important, and I’m surrounded by idiots!’ Both halves of this
proposition serve to conceal the jerk’s jerkitude from himself.
Thinking yourself important is a pleasantly self-gratifying excuse for
disregarding the interests and desires of others. Thinking that the people
around you are idiots seems like a good reason to disregard their intellectual
perspectives. As you ascend the hierarchy, you will find it easier to discover
evidence of your relative importance (your big salary, your first-class seat)
and of the relative idiocy of others (who have failed to ascend as high as
you). Also, flatterers will tend to squeeze out frank, authentic critics.
This isn’t
the only possible explanation for the prevalence of powerful jerks, of course.
Maybe jerks are actually more likely to rise in business and academia than
non-jerks – the truest sweethearts often suffer from an inability to advance
their own projects over the projects of others. But I suspect the causal path
runs at least as much in the other direction. Success might or might not favour the existing jerks, but I’m pretty sure it nurtures
new ones.
*
The moralistic jerk is an animal worth
special remark. Charles Dickens was a master painter of the type: his teachers,
his preachers, his petty bureaucrats and self-satisfied businessmen, Scrooge
condemning the poor as lazy, Mr Bumble shocked that
Oliver Twist dares to ask for more, each dismissive of the opinions and desires
of their social inferiors, each inflated with a proud self-image and ignorant
of how they are rightly seen by those around them, and each rationalising
this picture with a web of moralising ‘should’s.
Scrooge and
Bumble are cartoons, and we can be pretty sure we aren't as bad as them. Yet I
see in myself and all those who are not pure sweethearts a tendency to rationalise
my privilege with moralistic sham justifications. Here’s my reason for trying
to dishonestly wheedle my daughter into the best school, my reason why the
session chair should call on me rather than on the grad student who got her
hand up earlier, my reason why it’s fine that I have 400 library books in my
office…. Philosophers seem to have a special talent for this: we can concoct a
moral rationalisation for anything, with enough work!
(Such skill at rationalisation might explain why
ethicist philosophers seem to behave no morally better, on average, than
comparison groups of non-ethicists, as my collaborators and I have found in a
series of empirical studies looking at a broad range of issues from library
book theft and courteous behaviour at professional
conferences to rates of charitable donation and Nazi party membership in the
1930s.) The moralistic jerk’s rationalisations
justify his disregard of others, and his disregard of others prevents him from
accepting an outside corrective on his rationalisations,
in a self-insulating cycle. Here’s why it’s fine for me to proposition my
underlings and inflate my expense claims, you idiot critics. Coat the whole thing, if you like, in a patina of academic jargon.
The moralising jerk is apt to go badly wrong in his moral
opinions. Partly this is because his morality tends to be self-serving, and
partly it’s because his disrespect for others’ perspectives puts him at a
general epistemic disadvantage. But there’s more to it than that. In failing to
appreciate others’ perspectives, the jerk almost inevitably fails to appreciate
the full range of human goods – the value of dancing, say, or of sports,
nature, pets, local cultural rituals, and indeed anything that he doesn’t care
for himself. Think of the aggressively rumpled scholar who can’t bear the
thought that someone would waste her time getting a manicure. Or think of the
manicured socialite who can’t see the value of dedicating one’s life to dusty
Latin manuscripts. Whatever he’s into, the moralising
jerk exudes a continuous aura of disdain for everything else.
Furthermore,
mercy is near the heart of practical,
lived morality. Virtually everything that everyone does falls short of
perfection: one’s turn of phrase is less than perfect, one arrives a bit late,
one’s clothes are tacky, one’s gesture irritable, one’s choice somewhat
selfish, one’s coffee less than frugal, one’s melody trite. Practical mercy
involves letting these imperfections pass forgiven or, better yet, entirely
unnoticed. In contrast, the jerk appreciates neither
others’ difficulties in attaining all the perfections that he attributes to
himself, nor the possibility that some portion of what he regards as flawed is
in fact blameless. Hard moralising principle
therefore comes naturally to him. (Sympathetic mercy is natural to the
sweetheart.) And on the rare occasions when the jerk is merciful, his indulgence is usually ill-tuned: the flaws he
forgives are exactly the one he recognises in himself
or has ulterior reasons to let slide. Consider another brilliant literary
cartoon jerk: Severus Snape, the infuriating potions
teacher in J K Rowling’s novels, always eager to drop the hammer on Harry
Potter or anyone else who happens to annoy him,
constantly bristling with indignation, but wildly off the mark – contrasted
with the mercy and broad vision of Dumbledore.
Despite the
jerk’s almost inevitable flaws in moral vision, the moralising
jerk can sometimes happen to be right about some specific important issue (as Snape proved to be) – especially if he adopts a big social
cause. He needn’t care only about money and prestige. Indeed, sometimes an
abstract and general concern for moral or political principles serves as a kind
of substitute for genuine concern about the people in his immediate field of
view, possibly leading to substantial self-sacrifice. And in social battles,
the sweetheart will always have some disadvantages: the sweetheart’s talent for
seeing things from his opponent’s perspective deprives him of bold
self-certainty, and he is less willing to trample others for his ends. Social
movements sometimes do well when led by a moralising
jerk. I will not mention specific examples, lest I err and offend.
*
How can you
know your own moral character? You can try a label on for size: ‘lazy’, ‘jerk’,
‘unreliable’ – is that really me? As the work of Vazire and other personality
psychologists suggests, this might not be a very illuminating approach. More
effective, I suspect, is to shift from first-person reflection (what am I like?) to second-person description
(tell me, what am I like?). Instead
of introspection, try listening. Ideally, you will have a few people in your
life who know you intimately, have integrity, and are concerned about your
character. They can frankly and lovingly hold your flaws up to the light and
insist that you look at them. Give them the space to do this, and prepare to be
disappointed in yourself.
Done well
enough, this second-person approach could work fairly well for traits like
laziness and unreliability, especially if their scope is restricted:
laziness-about-X, unreliability-about-Y. But as I suggested above, jerkitude is
not so tractable, since if one is far enough gone, one can’t listen in the
right way. Your critics are fools, at least on this particular topic (their
critique of you). They can’t appreciate your perspective, you think – though
really it’s that you can’t appreciate theirs.
To discover
one’s degree of jerkitude, the best approach might be neither (first-person)
direct reflection upon yourself nor (second-person)
conversation with intimate critics but rather something more third-person:
Looking in general at other people.
Everywhere you turn, are you surrounded by fools, by boring nonentities, by
faceless masses and foes and suckers and, indeed, jerks?
Are you the only competent, reasonable person to be found? In other words, how
familiar was the vision of the world I described at the beginning of this
essay?
If your
self-rationalising defenses are low enough to feel a
little pang of shame at the familiarity of that vision of the world, then you
probably aren’t pure diamond-grade jerk. But who is? We’re all somewhere in the
middle. That’s what makes the jerk’s vision of the world so instantly
recognizable. It’s our own vision. But, thankfully, only
sometimes.