The Moral Lives of Ethicists,
or
How Often Do Ethics
Professors Call Their Mothers?
Eric
Schwitzgebel
Aeon
Magazine
featured article, July 14, 2015
None
of the classic questions of philosophy are beyond a seven-year-old’s understanding. If God exists, why do bad things
happen? How do you know there’s still a world on the other side of that closed
door? Are we just made of material stuff that will turn into mud when we die?
If you could get away with killing and robbing people just for fun, would you?
The questions are natural. It’s the answers that are hard.
Eight
years ago, I’d just begun a series of empirical studies on the moral behaviour of professional ethicists. My son Davy, then
seven years old, was in his booster seat in the back of my car. ‘What do you
think, Davy?’ I asked. ‘People who think a lot about what’s fair and about
being nice – do they behave any better than other people? Are they more likely
to be fair? Are they more likely to be nice?’
Davy
didn’t respond right away. I caught his eye in the rearview mirror.
‘The
kids who always talk about being fair and sharing,’ I recall him saying,
‘mostly just want you to be fair to them and share with them.’
When
I meet an ethicist for the first time – by ‘ethicist’, I mean a professor of
philosophy who specialises in teaching and researching
ethics – it’s my habit to ask whether ethicists behave any differently to other
types of professor. Most say no.
I’ll
probe further: why not? Shouldn’t regularly thinking about ethics have some
sort of influence on one’s own behaviour? Doesn’t it
seem that it would?
To
my surprise, few professional ethicists seem to have given the question much
thought. They’ll toss out responses that strike me as flip or are easily
rebutted, and then they’ll have little to add when asked to clarify. They’ll say
that academic ethics is all about abstract problems and bizarre puzzle cases,
with no bearing on day-to-day life – a claim easily shown to be false by a few
examples: Aristotle on virtue, Kant on lying, Singer on charitable donation.
They’ll say: ‘What, do you expect epistemologists to
have more knowledge? Do you expect doctors to be less likely to smoke?’ I’ll
reply that the empirical evidence does suggest that doctors are less likely to
smoke than non-doctors of similar social and economic background. Maybe
epistemologists don’t have more knowledge, but I’d hope that specialists in
feminism would exhibit less sexist behaviour – and if
they didn’t, that would be an interesting finding. I’ll suggest that
relationships between professional specialisation and
personal life might play out differently for different cases.
It
seems odd to me that our profession has so little to say about this matter. We criticise Martin Heidegger for his Nazism, and we wonder
how deeply connected his Nazism was to his other philosophical views. But we
don’t feel the need to turn the mirror on ourselves.
The
same issues arise with clergy. In 2010, I was presenting some of my work at the
Confucius Institute for Scotland. Afterward, I was approached by not one but two
bishops. I asked them whether they thought that clergy, on average, behaved
better, the same or worse than laypeople.
‘About
the same,’ said one.
‘Worse!’
said the other.
No
clergyperson has ever expressed to me the view that clergy behave on average
morally better than laypeople, despite all their immersion in religious
teaching and ethical conversation. Maybe in part this is modesty on behalf of
their profession. But in most of their voices, I also hear something that
sounds like genuine disappointment, some remnant of the young adult who had
headed off to seminary hoping it would be otherwise.
In a
series of empirical studies – mostly in collaboration with the philosopher
Joshua Rust of Stetson University – I have empirically explored the moral behaviour of ethics professors. As far as I’m aware, Josh
and I are the only people ever to have done so in a systematic way.
Here
are the measures we looked at: voting in public elections, calling one’s
mother, eating the meat of mammals, donating to charity, littering, disruptive
chatting and door-slamming during philosophy presentations, responding to
student emails, attending conferences without paying registration fees, organ
donation, blood donation, theft of library books, overall moral evaluation by
one’s departmental peers based on personal impressions, honesty in responding
to survey questions, and joining the Nazi party in 1930s Germany.
Obviously
some of these measures are more significant than others. They range from
comparative trivialities (littering) to substantial life decisions (joining the
Nazis), and from contributions to strangers (blood donation) to personal
interactions (calling Mom). Some of our measures rely on self-report (we didn’t
ask ethicists’ mothers how long it had really
been).
The
majority, however, were directly observational or involved peer testimony or
archival data. In several cases we had both self-reports and more objective
data. For example, we were able to compare philosophers’ self-reported voting
rates with state records showing whether and how often they had actually voted.
We found no evidence that ethicists’ self-reports of their behaviour were either more or less accurate than other
groups’ self-reports.
Ethicists
do not appear to behave better. Never once have we found ethicists as a whole
behaving better than our comparison groups of other professors, by any of our
main planned measures. But neither, overall, do they seem to behave worse.
(There are some mixed results for secondary measures.) For the most part,
ethicists behave no differently from professors of any other sort – logicians,
chemists, historians, foreign-language instructors.
Nonetheless,
ethicists do embrace more stringent moral norms on some issues, especially
vegetarianism and charitable donation. Our results on vegetarianism were particularly
striking. In a survey of professors from five US states, we found that 60 per
cent of ethicist respondents rated ‘regularly eating the meat of mammals, such
as beef or pork’ somewhere on the ‘morally bad’ side of a nine-point scale
ranging from ‘very morally bad’ to ‘very morally good’. By contrast, only 19
per cent of non-philosophy professors rated it as bad. That’s a pretty big
difference of opinion! Non-ethicist philosophers were intermediate, at 45 per
cent. But when asked later in the survey whether they had eaten the meat of a
mammal at their last evening meal, we found no statistically significant
difference in the groups’ responses – about 38 per cent of professors from all
groups reported having done so (including 37 per cent of ethicists).
Similarly
for charitable donation. In the same survey, we asked respondents what percentage of
income, if any, the typical professor should donate to charity, and then later
we asked what percentage of income they personally had given in the previous
calendar year. Ethicists espoused the most stringent norms: their average
recommendation was 7 per cent, compared with 5 per cent for the other two
groups. However, ethicists did not report having given a greater percentage of
income to charity than the non-philosophers (4 per cent for both groups). Nor
did adding a charitable incentive to half of our surveys (a promise of a $10
donation to their selected charity from a list) increase ethicists’ likelihood
of completing the survey. Interestingly, the non-ethicist philosophers, though
they reported having given the least to charity (3 per cent), were the only
group that responded to our survey at detectably higher rates when given the
charitable incentive.
Should
we expect ethicists to behave especially morally well as a result of their
training – or at least more in accord with the moral norms that they themselves
espouse?
Perhaps
we can defend a ‘no’. Consider this thought experiment:
An ethics
professor teaches Peter Singer’s arguments for vegetarianism to her
undergraduates. She says she finds those arguments sound and that in her view
it is morally wrong to eat meat. Class ends, and she goes to the cafeteria for
a cheeseburger. A student approaches her and expresses surprise at her eating
meat. (If you don’t like vegetarianism as an issue, another example could
serve: marital fidelity, charitable donation, fiscal honesty, courage in defence of the weak.)
‘Why
are you surprised?’ asks our ethicist. ‘Yes, it is morally wrong for me to
enjoy this delicious cheeseburger. However, I don’t aspire to be a saint. I
aspire only to be about as morally good as others around me. Look around this
cafeteria. Almost everyone else is eating meat. Why should I sacrifice this
pleasure, wrong though it is, while others do not? Indeed, it would be unfair
to hold me to higher standards just because I’m an ethicist. I am paid to
teach, research and write, like every other professor. I am paid to apply my
scholarly talents to evaluating intellectual arguments about the good and bad,
the right and wrong. If you want me also to live as a role model, you ought to
pay me extra!
‘Furthermore,’
she continues, ‘if we demand that ethicists live according to the norms they
espouse, that will put major distortive pressures on the field. An ethicist who
feels obligated to live as she teaches will be motivated to avoid highly
self-sacrificial conclusions, such as that the wealthy should give most of
their money to charity or that we should eat only a restricted subset of foods.
Disconnecting professional ethicists’ academic enquiries from their personal
choices allows them to consider the arguments in a more even-handed way. If no
one expects us to act in accord with our scholarly opinions, we are more likely
to arrive at the moral truth.’
‘In
that case,’ replies the student, ‘is it morally okay for me to order a
cheeseburger too?’
‘No!
Weren’t you listening? It would be wrong. It’s wrong for me, also, as I just
admitted. I recommend the avocado and sprouts. I hope that Singer’s and my
arguments help create a culture permanently free of the harms to animals and
the environment that are caused by meat-eating.’
‘This
reminds me of Thomas Jefferson’s attitude toward slave ownership,’ I imagine
the student replying. Maybe the student is black.
‘Perhaps
so.
Jefferson was a great man. He had the courage to recognise
that his own lifestyle was morally odious. He acknowledged his mediocrity and
resisted the temptation to try to paper over things with shoddy arguments.
Here, have a fry.’
Let’s
call this view cheeseburger ethics.
Any
of us could easily become much morally better than we are, if we chose to. For
those of us who are affluent by global standards, the path is straightforward:
spend less on luxuries and give the savings to a good cause. Even if you are
not affluent by global standards, unless you are on the precipice of ruin, you
could give more of your time to helping others. It’s not difficult to see
multiple ways, every day, in which one could be kinder to those who would
especially benefit from kindness.
And
yet, most of us choose moral mediocrity instead. It’s not that we try but fail,
or that we have good excuses. We – most of us – actually aim at mediocrity. The
cheeseburger ethicist is perhaps only unusually honest with herself about this.
We aspire to be about as morally good as our peers. If others cheat and get
away with it, we want to do the same. We don’t want to suffer for goodness
while others laughingly gather the benefits of vice. If the morally good life
is uncomfortable and unpleasant, if it involves repeated painful sacrifices
that are not compensated in some way, sacrifices that others are not also
making, then we don’t want it.
Recent
empirical work in moral psychology, especially by Robert B Cialdini,
professor emeritus at Arizona State University, seems to confirm this general
tendency. People are more likely to comply with norms that they see others
following, less likely to comply with norms when they see others violating
them. Also, empirical research on ‘moral self-licensing’ suggests that people
who act well on one occasion use that as an excuse to act less well on a
subsequent one. We gaze around us, then aim for so-so.
What,
in that case, is moral reflection good for? Here’s one thought. Perhaps it
gives us the power to calibrate more precisely toward our chosen level of moral
mediocrity. I sit on the couch, resting while my wife cleans up from dinner. I
know that it would be morally better to help than to continue relaxing. But how
bad, exactly, would it be for me not to help? Pretty bad?
Only a little bad? Not at all bad, but also not as
good as I would like to be if I weren’t feeling so lazy? These are the
questions that occupy my mind. In most cases, we already know what is good. No
special effort or skill is required to figure that out. Much more interesting
and practical is the question of how far short of the ideal we are comfortable
being.
Suppose
it’s generally true that we aim for goodness only by relative, rather than
absolute, standards. What, then, should we expect to be the effect of
discovering, say, that it is morally bad to eat meat, as the majority of US
ethicists seem to think? If you’re trying to be only about as good as others,
and no better, then you can keep enjoying the cheeseburgers. Your behaviour might not change much at all. What would change
is this: you would acquire a lower opinion of (almost) everyone’s behaviour, your own included.
You
might hope that others will change. You might advocate general societal change
– but you’ll have no desire to go first. Like Jefferson maybe.
I was
enjoying dinner in an expensive restaurant with an eminent ethicist, at the end
of an ethics conference. I tried these ideas out on him.
‘B+,’
he said. ‘That’s what I’m aiming for.’
I
thought, but did not say, B+ sounds good.
Maybe that’s what I’m aiming for, too. B+ on the great moral
curve of white middle-class college-educated North Americans. Let others
get the As.
Then
I thought, most of us who are aiming for B+ will
probably fall well short of that. You know, because we fool ourselves. Here I
am, away from my children again, at a well-funded conference in a beautiful
$200-a-night hotel, mainly, I suspect, so that I can nurture and enjoy my
rising prestige as a philosopher. What kind of person am I? What kind of
father? B+?
(Oh,
it’s excusable! – I hear myself saying. I’m a model of career success for the
kids, and of independence. And morality isn’t so demanding. And my
philosophical work is a contribution to the general social good. And I give,
um, well, a little to charity, so that makes up for it. And I’d be too
disheartened if I couldn’t do this kind of thing, which would make me worse as
a father and as a teacher of ethics. Plus, I owe it to myself. And… Wow, how neatly what I want to do fits with what’s
ethically best, once I think about it!)
Most
of the ancient philosophers and the great moral visionaries of the religious
wisdom traditions, East and West, would find the cheeseburger ethicist strange.
Most of them assumed that the main purpose of studying ethics was
self-improvement. Most of them also accepted that philosophers were to be
judged by their actions as much as by their words. A great philosopher was, or
should be, a role model: a breathing example of a life well-lived. Socrates
taught as much by drinking the hemlock as by any of his dialogues, Confucius by
his personal correctness, Siddhartha Gautama by his renunciation of wealth,
Jesus by washing his disciples’ feet. Socrates does not say: ethically, the
right thing for me to do would be to drink this hemlock, but I will flee
instead! (Maybe he could have said this, but then he would have been a
different sort of model.)
I’d
be suspicious of any 21st-century philosopher who offered up her- or himself as
a model of wise living. This is no longer what it is to be a philosopher – and
those who regard themselves as wise are in any case almost always mistaken.
Still, I think, the ancient philosophers got something right that the
cheeseburger ethicist gets wrong.
Maybe
it’s this: I have available to me the best attempts of earlier generations to
express their ethical understanding of the world. I even seem to have some
advantages over ancient philosophers, in that there are now many more
generations who have left written texts and several distinct cultures with long
traditions of written philosophy that I can compare. And I am paid, quite
handsomely by global standards, to devote a large portion of my time to
thinking through this material. What shall I do with this amazing opportunity?
Use it to get some publications and earn praise from my peers, as well as a
higher salary? Sure. Use it – as my seven-year-old son observed – as a tool to
badger others into treating me better? Okay, I guess so, sometimes. Use it to
try to shape other people’s behaviour in a way that
will make the world a generally better place? Simply enjoy its power and beauty
for its own sake? Yes, those things too.
But
also, it seems a waste not to try to use it to make myself a little ethically
better than I currently am. Part of what I find unnerving about the
cheeseburger ethicist is that she seems so comfortable with her mediocrity, so
uninterested in deploying her philosophical tools toward self-improvement.
Presumably, if approached in the right way, the great traditions of moral
philosophy have the potential to help us become morally better people. But in
cheeseburger ethics, that potential is cast aside.
The
cheeseburger ethicist risks intellectual failure as well. Real engagement with
a philosophical doctrine probably requires taking some steps toward living it.
The person who takes, or at least tries to take, personal steps toward Kantian
scrupulous honesty, or Mozian impartiality, or
Buddhist detachment, or Christian compassion, gains a kind of practical insight
into those doctrines that is not easily achieved through intellectual
reflection alone. A full-bodied understanding of ethics requires some living.
What’s
more, abstract doctrines lack specific content if they aren’t tacked down in a
range of concrete examples. Consider the doctrine ‘treat everyone as moral
equals who are worthy of respect’. What counts as adhering to this norm, and
what constitutes a violation of it? Only when we understand how norms play out
across examples do we really understand them. Living our norms, or trying to
live them, forces a maximally concrete confrontation with examples. Does your
ethical vision really require that you free the slaves on which
your lifestyle crucially depends? Does it require giving away your salary
and never again enjoying an expensive dessert? Does it require drinking the
hemlock if your fellow citizens unjustly demand that you do so?
Few
professional ethicists really are cheeseburger ethicists, I think, when they
stop to consider it. We do want our ethical reflections to improve us morally,
a little bit. But here’s the catch: we aim only to become a little morally better. We cut ourselves slack when we look at
others around us. We grade ourselves on a curve and aim for B+ rather than A.
And at the same time, we excel at rationalisation and
excuse-making – maybe more so, the more ethical theories we have ready to hand.
So we end, on average, about where we began, behaving more or less the same as
others of our social group.
Should
we aim for ‘A+’, then? Being frank with myself, I don’t want the self-sacrifice
I’m pretty sure would be involved in that. Should I aim at least a little
higher than B+? Shall I resolutely aim to be morally far better than my peers –
A or maybe A- – even if not quite a saint? I worry that needing to see myself
as unusually morally excellent is as likely to increase self-deception, rationalisation, and licensing as to actually improve me.
Shall
I redouble my efforts to be kinder and more generous, coupling them with
reminders of humility about my likelihood of success? Yes, I will – today! But
I already feel my resentment building, and I haven’t done anything yet. Maybe I
can escape that resentment by adjusting my sense of ‘mediocrity’ upward. I
might try to recalibrate by surrounding myself with like-minded peers in
virtue. But avoiding the company of those I deem morally inferior seems more
characteristic of the moralising jerk than of the
genuinely morally good person, and the history of efforts to establish
ethically unified organisations is discouraging.
I
can’t quite see my way forward. But now I worry that this, too, is excuse-making.
Nothing will assure success, so (phew!) I can comfortably stay in the same old
mediocre place I’m accustomed to. Such defeatism also fits nicely with one
natural way to read Josh Rust’s and my data: since ethicists don’t behave
better or worse than others, philosophical reflection must be behaviourally inert, taking us only where we were already
headed, its power mainly that of providing different words by which to decorate
our pre-determined choices. So I’m not to be blamed if all my ethical philosophising has not improved me.
I
reject that view. Instead, I favour this less
comfortable idea: philosophical reflection does have the power to move us, but
it is not a tame thing. It takes us where we don’t intend or expect, sometimes
one way, as often the other, sometimes amplifying our vices and illusions,
sometimes giving real insight and inspiring substantial moral change. These tendencies
cross-cut and cancel in complex ways that are difficult to detect empirically.
If we could tell in advance which direction our reflection would carry us and
how, we’d be implementing a set educational technique rather than challenging
ourselves philosophically.
Genuine
philosophical thinking critiques its prior strictures, including even the
assumption that we ought to be morally good. It damages almost as often as it
aids, is free, wild and unpredictable, always breaks
its harness. It will take you somewhere, up, down, sideways – you can’t know in
advance. But you are responsible for trying to go in the right direction with
it, and also for your failure when you don’t get there.