The
Self-Reported Moral Behavior of Ethics Professors
Eric Schwitzgebel
Department of Philosophy
University of California
Riverside, CA
92521-0201
eschwitz at domain: ucr.edu
Joshua Rust
Department of Philosophy, Unit 8250
Stetson University
421 North Woodland Boulevard
DeLand, FL
32723
joshuarust at domain: gmail.com
March 16, 2011
The
Self-Reported Moral Behavior of Ethics Professors
Abstract:
We
examine the self-reported moral attitudes and moral behavior of 198 ethics
professors, 208 non-ethicist philosophers, and 167 professors in departments
other than philosophy on eight moral issues: academic society membership,
voting, staying in touch with one’s mother, vegetarianism, organ and blood
donation, responsiveness to student emails, charitable giving, and honesty in
responding to survey questionnaires. On
some issues we also had direct behavioral measures that we could compare with
self-report. Ethicists expressed
somewhat more stringent normative attitudes on some issues, such as
vegetarianism and charitable donation.
However, on no issue did ethicists show significantly better behavior
than the two comparison groups. Our
findings on attitude-behavior consistency were mixed: Ethicists showed the
strongest relationship between behavior and expressed moral attitude regarding
voting but the weakest regarding charitable donation.
IRB approval: U.C. Riverside
HRRB HS-09-002
Word Count: 12,434
(excluding title page, abstract page, footnotes, and figure captions), plus
3,797 words of footnotes and six figures
Keywords: ethics, moral
psychology, moral behavior, attitude-behavior consistency, experimental
philosophy, applied ethics, vegetarianism, charity, voting
The Self-Reported Moral
Behavior of Ethics Professors
1. Introduction.
Do philosophy professors specializing in ethics behave,
on average, any morally better than do other professors? If not, do they at least behave more
consistently with their espoused values?
These questions have never been systematically studied.
One might find these questions interesting for several
reasons, but our primary aim is to understand the relationship between moral
reflection, especially the kinds of moral reflection practiced by professional
philosophers, and moral behavior.
Suppose that professional ethicists behave, overall, somewhat morally
better than do comparison groups of professors not specializing in ethics. Suppose, for example, that ethicists donate
more of their income to charity or eat a more vegetarian diet or donate blood
more frequently than do other professors – and assume, furthermore, that such
behavior is morally good. That discovery
would seem to invite, though it would not compel, certain optimistic thoughts
about the consequences of philosophical moral reflection. Alternatively, suppose that ethicists are no
more likely to do any of these things or even, perhaps, less likely. That discovery would seem to invite, though
it would not compel, certain pessimistic thoughts about the practical consequences
of philosophical moral reflection. Likewise,
suppose we found either that ethicists are more likely or that they are less
likely to act in accord with their espoused norms than are other
professors. That discovery, too, would
fit more naturally with some views of the relationship between philosophical
reflection and lived behavior than with other views.
Many philosophers, historically, have suggested that
studying philosophical ethics – or at least studying it in the right way – will
tend to improve moral behavior.
Aristotle, for example, hoped so; he said that the aim of studying
ethics was “not the attainment of theoretical knowledge” but rather “to become
good” (4th c. BCE/1962, 1103b).
The ancient Confucians and Stoics sought personal improvement through
philosophical reflection (as emphasized by Ivanhoe 1993/2000 and Hadot
1995). Kant sees moral philosophy as
arming us with reason against the corrupting force of our wishes and
inclinations (1785/2002, p. 206 [4:405]).
Mill portrays philosophical disputation as crucial to maintaining the
lively motivational force of ethical doctrines and religious creeds, which
otherwise become hollow formularies (1859/2003, p. 118). Peter Singer aims to induce vegetarianism and
charitable donation in his readers (e.g., 1972, 1975/2002).
Others have expressed doubts about the practical
effects of philosophical moral reflection, at least as normally practiced. Bernard Williams (1985) and Annette Baier
(1985) argue that philosophical ethics can undercut our intuitive sense of
what’s right. Hans-Georg Moeller (2009)
argues that philosophical moralizing tends to promote retributive
violence. Richard Posner (1999) and
Joshua Knobe and Brian Leiter (2007) argue that philosophical moral reasoning
is largely post-hoc rationalization of antecedent opinions and is largely
powerless to influence behavior. Despite
this difference in focus, the pessimistic and optimistic strains in the
tradition can be reconciled if philosophical moral reflection as ordinarily practiced, and standard philosophical moral education,
is toxic or inert but a superior way is available. That is, perhaps, not an uncommon view –
though of course there is no consensus about what the superior way might be.
The possibilities are manifold, the relationships
complex, and systematic empirical data almost entirely lacking. To help fix ideas, consider as reference
points the following four simple hypotheses about the relationship between
philosophical moral reflection and practical moral behavior. By “philosophical moral reflection” we mean
simply whatever type of cognition philosophers tend to engage in when they
bring their professional tools and competences to bear on moral issues.
Booster view: Philosophical moral
reflection leads to the discovery of moral truths – either general moral truths
that people tend to not to endorse absent such reflection (such as, perhaps,
that eating meat is morally bad: see Section 7 below) or particular moral
truths about specific situations that would not otherwise have been properly
morally appreciated (such as that some particular behavior toward which one is
tempted would be objectionably sexist). Such discoveries have a positive impact on
moral behavior – though perhaps only on average, to a moderate extent, and in
some areas. Furthermore, since it reveals
connections between specific instances of moral behavior and general moral
principles, philosophical moral reflection tends to increase the overall consistency
between one’s broad moral attitudes and one’s practical moral behavior.
Epiphenomenalist view: Philosophical moral
reflection is powerless to change moral behavior or moral attitudes, either for
better or for worse. It is behaviorally
inert and incapable of generating any new appreciation of moral truths. Whatever causal mechanisms generate our moral
attitudes and behavior, they are uninfluenced by our practices of philosophical
reflection. Thus, even heroic extremes
of philosophical reflection will neither improve one’s moral behavior nor
improve the alignment between general normative attitudes and practical
behavior.
Rationalization view: Philosophical moral
reflection tends to increase the consistency between attitudes and behavior, as
the booster suggests, but it does so in the opposite causal direction than the
booster suggests: The ethically reflective person’s attitudes shift to match
her behavior rather than her behavior shifting to match her attitudes. The reflective person’s practical behavior may
be unaffected by such rationalizations (the
inert rationalization view); or the tendency to rationalize may morally worsen
philosophically reflective people by freeing them to act on immoral impulses
that are superficially but unsatisfactorily justified by their reflections (the
toxic rationalization view). On the inert rationalization view, for
example, one will either steal or not steal a library book as a result of
psychological processes uninfluenced by one’s philosophical reflections, and
then one will shape one’s moral reflections to justify that incipient or
recently past behavior. On the toxic
rationalization view, one might feel an inclination to steal the book and act
on that inclination as a consequence of
a spurious moral justification for the theft.
Motivationally ineffectual
discovery view: As in the booster view, philosophical moral reflection tends to lead to
the discovery of moral truths. However, such
discoveries have no consequences for the practical behavior of the person
making those discoveries. Philosophical
reflection might lead one to discover, for example, that it is morally wrong to
eat the meat of factory-farmed mammals, but on this view one would continue to
eat factory-farmed meat at exactly the same rate as one would have done absent
any philosophical reflection on the matter.
To connect these views with our empirical research on
the moral behavior of ethicists requires the following two assumptions, which
we regard as empirically open but plausible to a first approximation. First: Professional ethicists tend to engage
in philosophical moral reflection, in ways pertinent to practical issues that arise
in their lives (i.e., not only at the highest level of abstraction or about
far-fetched hypothetical scenarios), more often than do socially similar
non-ethicists (and their philosophical moral reflection is at least as skillful). (Alternatively, one might hold that they reflect
more skillfully and at least as often.)
For example, lecturing on Kant on lying might increase ethicists’
propensity toward philosophical reflection when tempted to lie later in the
day; and ethicists might on average more extensively consider the philosophical
arguments for and against vegetarianism and charitable donation to famine
relief. Second: Professional ethicists
are similar to non-ethicist professors (either professors inside or outside of
philosophy – we use both comparison groups) in all dimensions relevant to moral
behavior except for their higher
rates of philosophical moral reflection.
For example, professional ethicists do not start out morally worse than
non-ethicists and then use philosophical moral reflection to improve themselves
up to average. With these two background
assumptions in hand, we derive the following empirical predictions from the
four views described above:
Moral behavior: The booster view predicts that
ethicists, since they engage in more philosophical moral reflection than
average, will behave morally better, on average, than do socially similar
non-ethicists. The epiphenomenalist,
inert rationalization, and motivationally ineffectual discovery views predict
that ethicists and non-ethicists will behave similarly. The toxic rationalization view predicts that
ethicists will behave morally worse.
Moral truth: If there are moral truths (or something
similar enough to moral truths; we recognize that the metaethical issues are
complex), the booster and motivationally ineffectual discovery views predict
that ethicists will be better in touch with those truths than are non-ethicists,
as a result of their greater tendency toward philosophical moral reflection. The epiphenomenalist view predicts that
ethicists and non-ethicists will be similarly in touch or out of touch with
moral truths. On the rationalization
view, ethicists’ moral judgments might be farther from the moral truth than
non-ethicists’, if the pressure of moral reflection toward attitude-behavior
consistency draws ethicists disproportionately toward erroneous moral attitudes
that superficially justify the bad behavior to which we are all tempted.
Attitude-behavior consistency: The booster view and
the rationalization view predict that ethicists’ higher rates of philosophical
moral reflection will lead them to show greater attitude-behavior consistency
than do non-ethicists (though the two views predict this result for different
reasons). The epiphenomenalist view
predicts that ethicists and non-ethicists will show similar levels of attitude-behavior
consistency. On the motivationally
ineffectual discovery view, ethicists might show less attitude-behavior
consistency than do non-ethicists, if ethicists’ skills help them escape the everyday
self-serving rationalizations that veil immoral behavior behind false principle.
We emphasize that these four views are simplistic and
underdeveloped. Many other and more
complex views are possible and, given the complexity of the human mind, perhaps
also more antecedently probable. These
views don’t do justice to the nuances of Aristotle, Mencius, Kant, Williams,
etc. We present them only as starting
points for reflection: With virtually no serious empirical data available on
the relationship between philosophical moral reflection and real-world moral
behavior, the range of plausible views remains relatively unconstrained. (There have been some studies of the effects
of business ethics and medical ethics courses, but never to our knowledge with
real-world moral behavior as the outcome measure.) Once data start coming in, we can begin to
constrain the models, including possibly ruling out, or at least creating
explanatory challenges for, the booster, the epiphenomenalist, the
rationalization view, the motivationally ineffectual discovery view, or all four
views.
2. An Overview of Our Research.
In several studies, we have begun to empirically
explore the moral behavior of ethics professors. So far we have found little evidence that
ethicists behave better. However, our
previous studies are neither broad-ranging enough nor univocal enough to create
more than prima facie explanatory challenges for the booster, nor have they
provided evidence on whether ethicists show lesser or greater attitude-behavior
consistency than do socially similar non-ethicists.
At a Pacific Division meeting of the American
Philosophical Association, we asked philosophers to anonymously evaluate the
overall moral behavior of arbitrarily selected ethicists in their own departments
and, for comparison, metaphysics and epistemology specialists in their own
departments. The majority of respondents
rated the ethicists no better than the M&E specialists (Schwitzgebel and
Rust 2009). In another study, we
examined publicly available voting records in five U.S. states (on the
assumption that voting is a duty), and we found that ethicists and political
philosophers voted neither more nor less often than did other professors
(though Political Science professors did vote more often; Schwitzgebel and Rust
2010). In other studies, we have found ethicists
neither more nor less likely than other professors to answer student emails
(Rust and Schwitzgebel in preparation) or to behave courteously at philosophy
conferences – though we did find that environmental ethicists left behind less
trash in their meeting rooms (Schwitzgebel, Rust, Huang, Moore, and Coates forthcoming). Ethics books also appear to go missing from
academic libraries more often than do other philosophy books (Schwitzgebel 2009).
In the research reported below, we extend our
explorations into several new domains of behavior, using self-report in a
multi-item questionnaire. The
disadvantages of self-report, perhaps especially self-report of moral or
immoral behavior, are well known; below we will discuss our strategies for
addressing these disadvantages. The
advantages of self-report are fourfold: First, it allows us to examine behavior
on which it is difficult to obtain good non-self-report data. We were especially interested in rates of
vegetarianism and rates of overall charitable donation because those issues are
widely discussed by ethicists, who often take explicit and concrete stances, with
attitude and behavior highly variable among professors. Thus, vegetarianism and charitable donation
seemed like promising areas to find substantial differences among groups’ moral
attitudes and behavior, if such differences exist. Second, a multi-item self-report
questionnaire allows us to examine respondents’ responses to several measures
simultaneously, potentially revealing trends invisible in single-shot
observational studies. Third, moral
attitude – as opposed to moral behavior – is for the most part accessible only
through self-report. And fourth, since
we already possessed data on the actual behavior of some of our respondents, we
were able to compare self-reported behavior with actual behavior, enabling
three-way comparisons between expressed moral attitude, self-described moral
behavior, and directly measured moral behavior; this also yielded a measure of
honesty in respondents’ survey replies – itself arguably a type of moral
behavior.
From February to March, 2009, we sent surveys to 337
ethicists, 329 non-ethicist philosophers, and 314 non-philosophers – all
tenured, tenure-track, or emeritus – from selected universities in five U.S.
states: California, Florida, North Carolina, Minnesota, and Washington State.[1] We chose these five states because we had
voting participation data for those states from a previous study (Schwitzgebel
and Rust 2010). We classified philosophy
recipients as ethicists or non-ethicists based on research interests stated on recipients’
academic homepages. (See Schwitzgebel
and Rust 2010 for details of the sampling and classification procedure.) All survey recipients received a preliminary
email about the survey, followed a few days later by an emailed link to a web
version of the survey (containing a unique tag for each participant). Unless they opted out of further
communications, recipients who did not complete the survey received first an
email reminder, then a hard copy of the survey with a return envelope, and then
a final email reminder. We received returned
surveys from 198 ethicists (59% of ethicist recipients), 208 non-ethicist
philosophers (63% of recipients), and 167 non-philosophers (53% of recipients),
for an overall response rate of 573 out of 980 (58%). Although responses were tagged with ID
numbers to enable comparisons of behavioral data and survey response data, no
identifying information about individuals, such as name or email address, was
stored with the survey responses.
The survey consisted of three sections. The first section contained ten questions
about normative attitude on nine moral issues: theft, academic society membership,
voting, staying in touch with one’s mother, vegetarianism, organ donation,
blood donation, responsiveness to student emails, and charity. Nine of the ten questions asked the
respondent to rate “the degree to which the action described is morally good or
morally bad” by checking one circle on a nine-point scale from “very morally
bad” (which we coded as 1) to “very morally good” (coded as 9), with the
midpoint labeled “morally neutral” and the 3 and 7 points labeled “somewhat
morally bad” and “somewhat morally good” respectively. In the hard copy of the survey, we cautioned
respondents that
We recognize that it may be difficult to rate moral
goodness and badness on a numerical scale, that different moral goods may be
incommensurable, and that the goodness or badness of an action can vary with
context. We encourage you to set aside
such concerns as best you are able, interpreting the questions below as
straightforwardly as possible. You are
welcome to clarify your answers, raise objections to the wording of the
questions, etc., in the margins.
The
web version of the survey contained the same caution, except concluding “At the
end of this section there will be a comment field in which are you are welcome
to clarify your answers, raise objections to the wording of the questions,
etc.”. We read all such clarifications
and critiques, but did not adjust responses in light of them; the
clarifications and critiques brought to light no unpredicted systematic
problems in the data. Respondents were
also permitted to leave questions blank, anywhere in the survey. We chose to solicit responses on a scale of
moral goodness rather than, say, a scale of rightness, permissibility, or
requirement, because the badness-goodness scale seemed to us conceptually the
simplest and the most symmetrical between the positive and negative sides.
The second part of the survey contained questions
about the respondent’s own behavior on eight of the nine issues above,
including further opportunity to comment in the margins or in web fields. The web version of the survey contained no
back button that would have permitted respondents to retrospectively alter
their normative responses in light of our questions about their personal
behavior, though a few respondents commented that they would have liked to do
so. We examined the hard-copy
questionnaires for signs of alteration of the normative responses but found
little evidence of such alteration. The
second part of the survey concluded with a normative question about dishonesty
in response to survey questions, followed by a self-report of honesty or
dishonesty. Despite the potential
sensitivity of questions about respondents’ personal behavior, respondents
skipped very few questions in our survey.[2]
Philosophy respondents’ questionnaires (both the
ethicists’ and the non-ethicists’) contained a third part consisting of two
questions. The first asked the
respondent to report the level of abstraction at which she tends to consider
ethicial issues (metaethics, normative ethics, applied ethics, no
ethics-related area among my specializations).
The second asked the respondent to report what normative ethical view
she finds broadly most appealing (deontological, consequentialist, virtue
ethical, skeptical, no settled position).
Half of the survey recipients were given a charity
incentive to complete the survey. We offered
to donate $10 to a charity of their choice from among Oxfam America, World
Wildlife Fund, CARE, Make-a-Wish Foundation, Doctors Without Borders, or
American Red Cross. (We kept our
promise, donating a total of $2,880 dollars to the selected charities.) The charity selection was the last question
of the survey, set aside in a section of its own. The charity incentive was partly intended to
enhance response rates. However, equally
importantly, it allowed us to look for group differences in responsiveness to
the charity incentive and in charity-response stability. (If a group gives similar responses to the
charity questions regardless of whether they received the charity incentive,
their responses are stable between the versions; if not, their responses are
unstable.)
A full facsimile of the survey is available online at
****.
Thus, our study is multi-faceted – illuminatingly so,
we hope. Proper presentation and
analysis of the results will necessarily be somewhat lengthy.
3. Theft of $1000.
As mentioned above, the survey began with ten
normative questions about nine moral issues.
Nine of the ten questions asked respondents to rate various actions on a
nine-point scale from “very morally bad” (1) to “very morally good” (9), with
“morally neutral” (5) in the middle. The
first of these questions was “stealing $1000 from a house where you are staying
as a guest”. This first question was
intended to help anchor the morally bad end of the scale, providing respondents
with an implicit comparison point for their other responses and aiding
interpretation of the scale. As
expected, virtually all respondents rated this action on the morally bad side
of the scale. All 573 respondents
answered this question, and only one of those 573, an ethicist, rated it above
3 on our scale (that respondent rated it 5, “morally neutral”). 76% of respondents rated this action at the
extreme end of the scale, that is, 1, “very morally bad”, and 96% rated the
action either 1 or 2.
Non-philosophers were significantly more likely to
rate the action at the extreme endpoint of the scale (92% rated it 1) than were
either ethicists or non-ethicist philosophers (74% and 65% respectively; for
ease of exposition, details of statistical tests will be confined to footnotes).[3] This might reflect a real difference in
opinion about the moral badness of theft, but we’re inclined to think that it
mostly reflects a scaling issue: Philosophers, accustomed to being presented
with murderous moral thought experiments, may have been more likely than
non-philosophers to have reserved the extreme bad end of the scale for
particularly heinous deeds. Because of
such scaling issues, as well as antecedent concerns about the meaningfulness of
small-to-moderate differences in mean response on our scales, we emphasize
qualitative differences in analyzing the normative questions – differences,
that is, between rating the action anywhere on the morally bad side of the
scale (1-4) vs. rating it as morally neutral (5) vs. rating it as morally good
(6-9).
We did not ask for self-report of theft.
4. Membership in Academic Societies.
The second normative question asked respondents to
rate “regularly paying membership dues to support one’s main academic
disciplinary society (the APA, the MLA, etc., as appropriate)” on our
nine-point scale from “very morally bad” to “very morally good”. We deliberately phrased this question
somewhat leadingly, in terms of “support” by paying dues, to highlight the
potential moral dimension of belonging to a disciplinary society. The three groups did not detectably differ in
the percentage rating societal membership as morally good: 66% of ethicists did
so, compared to 69% of non-ethicist philosophers and 65% of non-philosophers.[4] Neither did the groups differ much in their
mean responses on the scale: 6.3 for ethicists vs. 6.3 for non-ethicist
philosophers and 6.6 for non-philosophers.[5] Only three respondents rated membership on
the bad side of the scale (two ethicists, one non-ethicist philosopher).
Part II of the questionnaire was labeled “Behavior”
and began with the statement “The following questions pertain to YOUR OWN
behavior on the issues previously presented.”
The first question in Part II was
11. Are you currently a dues-paying member of your
discipline’s main academic society?”
¨ yes
¨ no
¨ don’t recall
Non-philosopher
respondents were marginally more likely to report societal membership: 87% did
so, compared to 78% of ethicists and 78% of non-ethicist philosophers.[6]
Before distributing the surveys, we had gathered data
on philosophy recipients’ membership in the American Philosophical Association
by examining the APA membership list. (We
emphasize that all data were coded to mask the identities of particular
individuals and that all aspects of our research were approved in advance by
the U.C. Riverside Human Research Review Board.) 68% of survey respondents appeared on the
membership list (67% of ethicists, 69% of non-ethicist philosophers), somewhat
lower than the self-reported rate of 78%.
Assuming that the APA membership lists accurately reflect membership
(there may be some small divergences), 44% of ethicist non-members falsely
reported membership, as did 39% of non-ethicist members (not statistically
different rates[7]) –
seemingly reflecting a bias toward “socially desirable responding”, that is, toward
giving answers that would appear to cast the respondent or the respondent’s
group in a good light. In Section 11
below, we will discuss the general issue of response accuracy or honesty and
whether it varies among the groups.
As one might expect, survey respondents – perhaps
because they are more responsive to professional inquiries or more active in
the research side of the profession – were more likely to be APA members than
were non-respondents: 68% of survey respondents were APA members, compared to
52% of non-respondents.[8] Non-response
bias is the tendency for survey respondents to differ from survey
non-respondents in one of the dimensions of interest. Accordingly, we note that positive attitudes
toward societal membership may be somewhat overrepresented among survey
respondents.
Among ethicists who rated membership on the morally
good side of our nine-point scale, 75% were members (as measured by presence on
the APA list), compared to 52% of ethicists who did not rate membership on the
morally good side of the scale; for non-ethicist philosophers, the
corresponding spread was 73% vs. 61%.[9] Thus, ethicists tended to show a stronger attitude-behavior
relationship than did non-ethicist philosophers. However, this trend did not approach
statistical significance.[10] Figure 1 displays these results graphically. In Section 14, we will address the issue of
whether ethicists show more consistency overall between their expressed
attitudes and their directly measured or self-reported behavior.
FIGURE
1: Relationship of expressed normative view about “regularly paying membership
dues to support one’s main academic disciplinary society (the APA, the MLA,
etc., as appropriate)” and appearance on the American Philosophical
Association’s membership list.
Increasing bar height from left to right reflects correlation between
behavior and normative view.
In sum: Regarding societal membership, we found no substantial
differences between ethicists and non-ethicist philosophers in normative
attitude, self-reported behavior, directly measured behavior, or accuracy of
response (which was low for APA non-members); there was a trend, but not
statistically significant, for ethicists to show a stronger attitude-behavior
relationship. Non-philosophers were
somewhat more likely than philosophers to self-report membership in their
disciplinary societies.
5. Voting in Public Elections.
Our third normative question asked respondents to rate
“regularly voting in public elections” on our usual nine-point scale from “very
morally bad” to “very morally good”.
Later, in Part II, we asked three self-report questions on voting
behavior:
12. Are you a United States citizen eligible to
vote?
¨ yes
¨ no
13. How many
public elections (including local, state, and national) would you estimate you
have voted in since Jan. 1, 2000 (including foreign elections if not a U.S.
citizen)?
enter a number ____
14. Did you vote in the November, 2008, U.S.
general Presidential election?
¨ yes
¨ no
¨ don’t recall
The response groups did not detectably differ in the percentage
who rated regularly voting as morally good: 90% of ethicists did so, compared
to 85% of non-ethicist philosophers and 89% of non-philosophers.[11] (Only one respondent, a non-ethicist
philosopher, rated voting as bad; the remaining 12% rated voting as morally
neutral.) The groups did differ in mean
response on the scale: Non-philosopher respondents gave a mean response of 7.8
on the nine-point scale, significantly higher than the 7.3 mean for ethicists
and 7.1 for non-ethicist philosophers, but we would interpret this difference
cautiously due to the scaling issues discussed in Section 3.[12]
Non-ethicist philosophers were somewhat less likely
than either ethicists or non-philosophers to report being a U.S. citizen
eligible to vote (84% vs. 91% and 93% respectively).[13] Excluding non-citizens, all three groups
reported voting at about the same rate: 9.2 times since the year 2000 for
ethicists, compared to 9.0 times for non-ethicist philosophers and 9.8 times
for non-philosophers.[14] Virtually all respondents who reported being
eligible to vote in the U.S. also reported voting in the 2008 U.S. general
Presidential election: an incredible 98% – all but six of the respondents. No respondent answered “don’t recall”.
For many of the survey respondents we had
identity-masked voting participation data, derived from state records, from a
previous study (Schwitzgebel and Rust 2010).
We updated those data for the present study, using a coding scheme that
converted names to unique identifiers (thus preventing us from drawing
inferences about particular voters’ survey responses). Among survey recipients, the mean number of
votes per year in state records was virtually identical for all groups: 1.09
for the ethicists, 1.12 for the non-ethicist philosophers, and 1.11 for the
non-philosophers.[15] The variance
in voting rates was also virtually identical: Ethicists did not show a broader
spread of voting habits (e.g., with an overrepresentation of ultra-conscientious
voters balanced against an overrepresentation of merely sporadic voters).[16]
Survey respondents voted somewhat more frequently than
non-respondents: 1.17 vs. 1.03 votes per year.[17] Voter participation and survey participation
might be related for any of a variety of reasons, such as illness, time
demands, interest in having one’s voice heard, or primary residence in a
different locale. We find the relatively
small difference in vote rate between respondents and non-respondents
encouraging on the issue of non-response bias.
Despite a tendency for Americans in general to
substantially overreport voting (Bernstein, Chadha, and Mountjoy 2001; Holbrook
and Krosnick 2010), we found no such tendency among our respondents. Virtually all of the respondents for whom we
could find voting records and who reported voting in the 2008 U.S. general
Presidential election did in fact vote in that election, reflecting an
astounding 96% participation rate overall (compared to 62% participation among
eligible U.S. citizens generally).[18] Though the numbers are somewhat small,
respondents for whom we had full voting records since the year 2000 tended to
slightly underreport voting, reporting having voted in an average of 9.2
elections since the year 2000, while voter records show them actually to have
voted in an average of 10.6 elections.[19] (This underreporting might reflect difficulty
remembering local elections and runoffs.)
Among the 88% of respondents who expressed the view
that voting is morally good, all three groups voted at virtually the same rate
according to state records: 1.19 votes per year for ethicists, compared to 1.17
votes per year for both the other groups.[20] The 12% who rated voting morally neutral
trended only slightly toward voting less often: 1.11 votes per year on average
(with numbers too small for meaningful statistical comparison between ethicists
and non-ethicists).[21] However, ethicists showed a significant
relationship between expressed normative attitude on the 1-9 scale and state-reported
voting frequency, with a correlation of .36 – compared to only .14 for the non-ethicist
philosophers and .01 for the non-philosophers.[22] In other words, non-philosophers’ expressed
attitude toward voting was unrelated to their measured voting rate, whereas
ethicists who expressed a strongly positive normative attitude toward voting
tended to vote more frequently than ethicists who did not. Figure 2 displays the results.
FIGURE 2: Relationship of expressed normative view
about “regularly voting in public elections” and voting rates derived from
public records. Increasing bar height
from left to right reflects correlation between behavior and normative
view. Notice that only the darkest bars,
for the ethicists, show this trend.
In sum, the groups differed little in overall
normative view and had virtually identical voting behavior overall, but
ethicists showed a stronger attitude-behavior relationship than the other
groups, with a substantially higher observed correlation between state records
of voting behavior and the strength of their expressed normative view.
6. Staying in Touch with Mom.
The fourth question of the survey asked respondents to
rate “not keeping in at least monthly face-to-face or telephone contact with
one’s mother” on the usual 1 to 9 scale from “very morally bad” to “very
morally good”. Self-report of behavior
occurred in Questions 15 and 16:
15. Over the
last two years, about how many times per month on average have you spoken with
your mother (face-to-face or on the phone)?
(If your mother is deceased, consider how often you spoke during her
last two years of life.)
¨ once (or less) every 2-3
months
¨ about once a month
¨ 2-4 times a month
¨ 5 times a month or more
16. About how
many days has it been since your last face-to-face or phone contact with your
mother?
enter a number in days (if
mother deceased enter ‘999’) ____
The
reader will be unsurprised to learn that for this question we had no direct measures
of behavior. As with many of our
behavioral self-report questions, we deliberately asked first a general question
that would be hard to answer accurately and easy to fudge and a more specific
question that would be easier to answer and harder to fudge. We did this as a way of checking for a bias
toward socially desirable responding, which we expected to reveal itself in
disparities between the general and specific answers (see especially Section 7
below).
Similar percentages of all three groups rated not
keeping in regular contact with one’s mother on the bad side of our scale: 73%
of ethicists, 74% of non-ethicist philosophers, and 71% of non-philosophers.[23] (3% rated it as morally good; our mothers
tell us they mistakenly flipped the scale due to the negative phrasing of the
question.) The groups also gave similar
mean responses: mean 3.4 for ethicists, compared to 3.7 for non-ethicist
philosophers and 3.3 for non-philosophers.[24]
Non-philosophers reported the most frequent
contact. If we accept the norm of at
least monthly contact, non-philosophers reported the least counternormative
behavior on the general question, with only 5% reporting contact less than once
a month, compared to 11% of ethicists and 12% of non-ethicist philosophers. 83% of non-philosophers reported contact at
least twice a month, compared to 70% of ethicists and 74% of non-ethicist
philosophers.[25] On the specific question about days since
contact, differences were more subtle, and not statistically significant, but
in the same direction: 8% of non-philosophers reported that it had been more
than 30 days since their last contact, compared to 10% of ethicists and 11% of
non-ethicist philosophers (excluding respondents reporting deceased mothers).[26] The log-transformed mean of the reported days
since last contact plus one was 5.0 for the non-philosophers, 5.9 for the
ethicists, and 6.7 for the non-ethicist philosophers.[27] These differences cannot be explained by
group differences in age (there were none) or in gender (which did not relate
to reported maternal contact). See
Section 13 for more demographic analysis.
Like the voting question but unlike the societal
membership question, respondents did not appear, overall, to show a social
desirability bias – at least insofar as such a bias would emerge as a
difference between the fudgeable general question and the presumably less
fudgeable recent-instance question.
Respondents reporting contact about once a month should, on average,
report about 15 days since last maternal contact; they actually reported a log-transformed
mean plus one of 12 days (38% reporting more than 14 days); those reporting 2-4
contacts per month had a mean of 5 days; and those reporting 5 or more had a
mean of 3 days; with all groups similar in this regard.[28]
Non-ethicist philosophers showed the strongest
relationship between expressed normative attitude and self-reported
behavior. Among non-ethicist
philosophers who expressed the view that it is bad not to keep in at least monthly
contact with one’s mother, 92% reported contact within the past 14 days, while
among non-ethicist philosophers who rated it as neutral or good 57% reported
contact within the past 14 days, a differential of 35%.[29] For ethicists, the corresponding percentages
were 84% vs. 77% (differential 7%); for non-philosophers 91% vs. 86%
(differential 15%).[30] Likewise, non-ethicist philosophers showed a
much larger correlation between normative response on the 1-9 scale and days
since last reported contact: .45, compared to .13 for ethicists and .09 for
non-philosophers.[31] Figure 3 displays these data graphically.
FIGURE 3: Relationship of expressed normative view
about “not keeping in at least monthly face-to-face or telephone contact with
one’s mother” and log-transformed mean of number of days, plus one, since self-reported
last face-to-face or telephone contact.
Increasing bar height from left to right reflects correlation between
behavior and normative view. Notice that
non-ethicist philosophers show the strongest correlation. Note also that non-philosophers show the
lowest mean (given approximately equal distribution among the attitudinal groups).
In sum, on this measure the non-philosophers reported
the most maternal contact and the non-ethicist philosophers showed the
strongest relationship between expressed normative view and self-reported
behavior, a pattern of results predicted by none of the simple models offered
in the introduction.
7. Vegetarianism.
Question 5 asked respondents to rate “regularly eating
the meat of mammals such as beef or pork” on the usual 1-9 normative scale. We asked about the meat of mammals to avoid
confusing respondents who see important moral differences between mammals and
other animals, but we saw no way to respect everyone’s moral distinctions
(e.g., the distinction between factory farmed and humanely raised meat) without
invoking further possibly confusing distinctions. (Indeed, similar considerations apply to all
our normative questions; we chose to err on the side of simplicity.) Questions 17 and 18 asked respondents to
report their own consumption of mammal meat:
17. During
about how many meals or snacks per week do you eat the meat of mammals such as
beef or pork?
enter number of times per
week ____
18. Think back
on your last evening meal, not including snacks. Did you eat the meat of a mammal during that
meal?
¨ yes
¨ no
¨ don’t recall
We
use the term vegetarianism to refer
to refraining from eating the meat of mammals.
By meat we mean to include
only the meat of mammals.
On this normative question, unlike the previous ones,
the groups differed enormously in their responses: 60% of ethicists rated
meat-eating on the bad side of the scale, compared to 45% of non-ethicist
philosophers and only 19% of non-philosophers.[32] (Approximately 5% of respondents in all
groups rated it as good.) Differences in
qualitative response were not as large but still large enough to be meaningful
(perhaps especially since they run opposite what would be predicted from the
scaling concerns discussed in Section 3): ethicists’ mean 4.0, non-ethicist
philosophers’ 4.2, and non-philosophers’ 4.7.[33]
In contrast, when asked about the previous evening
meal, the groups’ responses were only marginally statistically different and
ethicists were not even in the lowest group: 37% of ethicists reported eating
meat at their last evening meal, compared to 33% of non-ethicist philosophers
and 45% of non-philosophers.[34] Self-reported meals per week differed a little
more, with a mean of 4.1 self-reported meals per week for ethicists, compared
to 4.6 for non-ethicist philosophers and 5.3 for non-philosophers.[35] Strict vegetarianism seems morally and
psychologically rather different from merely low meat consumption, so we also
divided the meals/week responses into zeros and non-zeros. Here we did see a substantial group
difference: 27% of ethicists reported eating no mammal meat at all, compared to
20% of non-ethicist philosophers and 13% of non-philosophers.[36]
We found a bias toward underreporting meat consumption
among respondents reporting eating meat at 1-3 meals per week. 21% of respondents who reported eating meat
at one meal per week reported eating meat at the previous evening meal. Even if we assume that meat is only consumed at evening meals, the
number should be closer to 14% (1/7); if we assume, perhaps more plausibly,
that approximately half of all meat meals are evening meals, then the number
should be closer to 7%. Similarly, 30%
of respondents who reported two meat meals per week reported meat at the last
evening meal (vs. a target of 14%-29%), as did 51% of respondents who reported
three meals/week (vs. a target of 21%-43%).
This apparent bias toward socially desirable responding did not differ
between the groups: 18 of 54 ethicists in the 1-3 meals/week group reported eating
meat the previous night (33%), compared to 18 of 52 non-ethicist philosophers
(35%) and 14/40 non-philosophers (35%).[37] Two of the 110 respondents who reported 0
meals/week also reported having eaten meat at the previous evening meal (one
ethicist, one non-ethicist philosopher).
Expressed normative attitude and self-reported
behavior were significantly related for all three groups. Overall, 27% of respondents who rated eating
meat as bad reported eating it at the last evening meal, compared to 47% of
respondents who rated eating meat as neutral or good. The spread was 52% vs. 27% for ethicists, 37%
vs. 28% for non-ethicist philosophers, and 51% vs. 23% for non-philosophers;
and strength of expressed normative attitude predicted low likelihood of reporting
meat-eating at the last evening meal as is evident from Figure 4.[38]
FIGURE
4: Relationship of expressed normative attitude about “regularly eating the
meat of mammals such as beef or pork” and reporting having eaten the meat of a
mammal at the last evening meal.
Increasing bar height from left to right reflects correlation between
self-reported behavior and normative view.
Note the substantial relationship for all groups. Note also: The “1” column appears empty
because none of the twelve respondents giving that answer to the normative
question reported having eaten the meat of a mammal at the last evening meal.
In sum, ethicists were much more likely than
non-philosophers to rate eating the meat of mammals on the bad side of the
scale, while non-ethicist philosophers were intermediate. Ethicists were also substantially more likely
to self-report vegetarianism (that is, zero meat meals per week). However, when asked about their last evening
meal, ethicists reported eating meat at approximately the same rate as did the other
groups. All groups showed at least a
moderate relationship between expressed normative view and self-reported
behavior.
8. Organ and Blood Donation.
Question 6 asked respondents to rate “regularly
donating blood” on our usual 1-9 scale, and Question 7 asked respondents to
rate “not having on one’s driver’s license a statement or symbol indicating
willingness to be an organ donor in the event of death”. The behavioral self-report questions were:
19. Please look
at your driver’s license and indicate whether there is a statement or symbol
indicating your willingness to be an organ donor in the event of death.
¨ yes
¨ no
¨ driver’s license not
available
20. About how many times per year do you donate
blood?
¨ twice a year or more
¨ about once a year
¨ once every few years
¨ rarely or never
¨ not eligible to donate
blood
21. When was the last time you donated blood?
enter an approximate date (skip this question if you
have never donated)
MM /
DD / YYYY
____ ____
______
Philosophers, especially ethicists, were more likely
to rate donating blood as good and not being an organ donor as bad: 84% of
ethicists rated donating blood as good, compared to 80% of non-ethicist
philosophers and 72% of non-philosophers. And 60% of ethicists rated not having
a donor symbol as bad, compared to 56% of non-ethicist philosophers and 42% of
non-philosophers.[39]
Despite this difference in normative view,
self-reported behavior was virtually identical among the three groups. 68% of
ethicists, 65% of non-ethicist philosophers, and 69% of non-philosophers
reported having a donor symbol on their driver’s license (excluding six
respondents who reported an unavailable driver’s license).[40] Very few from any group reported donating twice
a year or more (4% of ethicists, 5% of non-ethicist philosophers, 2% of
non-philosophers) or even about once a year (4%, 5%, 5%). Most reported donating rarely or never (42%,
42%, 39%) or being ineligible (38%, 38%, 39%).
The percentage reporting having donated in 2008 or 2009 (excluding
ineligibles) was 13% of ethicists, 14% of non-ethicist philosophers, and 10% of
non-philosophers.[41]
We saw a small social desirability bias in reporting,
insofar as such a bias can be inferred from differences between the fudgeable
general question and the presumably less fudgeable recent-instance
question. Respondents reporting blood
donation twice a year or more reported a mean most recent donation of 2008.5,
those reporting about once a year reported a mean of 2007.4, and those
reporting once every few years reported a mean of 2004 – compared to expected means
of about 2009.0, 2008.7, and 2006.[42] The numbers were too small for meaningful
comparison of groups’ bias toward socially desirable responding.
The non-ethicist philosophers showed the strongest
relationship between expressed normative view and self-reported behavior on the
organ donation question but trended toward showing the weakest relationship on
the blood donation questions.[43] Figure 5 visually displays the organ donation
results. Due to the small number of
regular blood donors, the blood donation results do not admit of similar
graphical presentation.
FIGURE
5: Relationship of expressed normative view about “not having on one’s driver’s
license a statement or symbol indicating willingness to be an organ donor in
the event of death” and reporting having an organ donor statement or symbol on
driver’s license. Decreasing bar height
from left to right reflects correlation between self-reported behavior and normative
view. Note that non-ethicist
philosophers show the strongest trend.
9. Email Responsiveness.
Question 8 asked respondents to rate “not consistently
responding to student emails” on the usual 1-9 scale from “very morally bad” to
“very morally good”. Question 22 was:
22. About what
percentage of student emails do you respond to?
enter a percentage
______
We
also measured behavior directly by sending respondents up to three emails
designed to look as though they were from students, spread across the course of
almost a year. The emails concerned
office hours, declaring a major, and a request about a future class. They came from Yahoo and Gmail accounts, were
tested against spam filters, and always addressed the professor by name; some
of the emails contained specific information pertinent to the professor, such
as the name of course the professor was scheduled to teach in the upcoming term
(drawn from the schedule of courses at the professor’s university). Any non-automated reply was coded as a
“response”. We replaced identifying data
with unique tags in a way that prevented us from being able to determine the
responses of particular individuals; we were interested only in group trends. A more detailed discussion of our procedure
and results is available in Rust and Schwitzgebel (in preparation).
The groups did not differ in expressed normative attitude.
83% of ethicists rated
non-responsiveness to student emails on the morally bad side of the scale,
compared to 83% of non-ethicist philosophers and 85% of non-philosophers (1%
rated it good), with means of 3.4, 3.4, and 3.1, near the “somewhat morally
bad” label of the scale.[44]
Nor did the groups differ detectably in measured
behavior. Among survey respondents who
received all three emails, ethicists replied to a mean of 1.9 of our messages,
non-ethicist philosophers to a mean of 1.8, and non-philosophers to a mean of
1.9.[45] Survey respondents’ reply rates to each email
considered individually were also within statistical chance.[46]
Unsurprisingly, survey non-respondents were less
likely to reply to our email messages.
However the difference was not large: Among survey recipients who
received all three emails, the mean number of replies was 1.6 for the survey
non-respondents vs. 1.8 for the survey respondents.[47] We find this modest difference in the
predicted direction reassuring on the issue of survey non-response bias. Still, we expect that normative attitudes
toward email responsiveness and opinions about one’s own rate of responsiveness
may be a bit higher among survey respondents than in the target population as a
whole.
The groups also did not detectably differ in
self-reported email responsiveness. About
half of the respondents from all three groups claimed to respond to 100% of
student emails (49% of ethicists, 48% of non-ethicist philosophers, and 55% of
non-philosophers); and 84% of respondents claimed to respond to at least 95% of
student emails (82% of ethicists, 83% of non-ethicist philosophers, and 87% of
non-philosophers).[48] We are inclined to regard these self-reported
response rates as unrealistically high. There
were 122 respondents who claimed 100% responsiveness to student emails, who received
all three of our email messages, and who also took the electronic version of
our survey (thus confirming the validity of their recorded email address). Among these respondents, only 31% did in fact
reply to all three emails (39% replied to two, 25% to one, and 4% to none). One caveat, however, is this: In subsequent
discussion, some respondents suggested that they interpreted “student” to mean
something like “student whose name I recognize”; they would presumably not have
recognized the fictional names we used in our emails.
The relationship between self-reported email
responsiveness and responsiveness to our three email messages was very weak: a
correlation of only .14.[49]
Self-described email responsiveness thus
predicted only 2% of the variance in measured behavior. The correlation was highest for the
non-philosophers (r = .26, predicting 7% of the variance), intermediate and
marginally significant for the ethicists (r = .13, predicting 2% of the
variance), and essentially non-existent for the non-ethicist philosophers (r =
.06, predicting 0% of the variance).[50]
We classified the following pattern of responses to
our email questions as showing a suspicious tilt toward socially desirable
responding: a self-reported rate of 100% responsiveness to student emails and
failure to respond to at least one of the email messages we sent or a self-reported
rate of at least 95% responsiveness and responsiveness to fewer than 50% of the
emails we sent. The groups did not
differ by this measure: 38% of ethicist respondents fell into this pattern,
compared to 41% of non-ethicist philosophers and 40% of philosophers.[51]
Expressed normative attitude was also largely unpredictive of email responsiveness. The average reply rate to our emails for professors who rated not consistently responding to student emails on the bad side of the scale was 63%; for those who rated it as neutral (or good) the response rate was 61%. For ethicists, the spread was 65% vs. 61%, for non-ethicist philosophers 59% vs. 64% (actually trending in the unpredicted direction), and for non-philosophers 64% vs. 55%. All of these differences are within statistical chance.[52] Figure 6 displays these data visually.
Figure 6: Relationship of expressed normative attitude about “not consistently
responding to student emails” and mean percentage responsiveness to emails we
sent that were designed to appear as though from students. Decreasing bar height from left to right
reflects correlation between self-reported behavior and expressed normative attitude.
Expressed normative attitude was moderately correlated with self-reported response rate, especially among ethicists: For respondents as a whole the correlation was .26. For ethicists it was .38, for non-ethicist philosophers .24, and for non-philosophers .13.[53]
In sum, the groups showed no difference in their normative attitude about responsiveness to student emails, in their self-described email responsiveness, or in their measured responsiveness; expressed attitude about the morality of not consistently responding to student emails was not detectably related to measured email responsiveness for any of the groups; and self-reported email responsiveness was only very weakly related to measured responsiveness.
10. Charitable
Donation.
The last two questions of Part I concerned charitable donation. Question 9 asked respondents to rate “donating 10% of one’s income to charity” on the usual nine-point moral scale. Question 10 was:
About what percentage of income should the typical professor donate to charity? (Enter 0 if you think it’s not the case that the typical professor should donate to charity.)
enter a percentage from 0 to 100: _____
In Part II we asked:
23. In 2008, about what percentage of your annual income did you donate to charity?
enter a percentage from 0 to 100 (“0” if you never donated): _____
As
discussed in Section 2, half of the recipients received a $10 charity
incentive. This allowed us to examine
group differences in responsiveness to the charity incentive as a measure of
charitable behavior. As we will explain,
this manipulation also produced data about response stability and non-response
bias.
Ethicists expressed the strongest normative views favoring
charity: 89% of ethicists rated donating 10% of one’s income to charity as
morally good, compared to 85% of non-ethicist philosophers and 73% of
non-philosophers (3% of respondents rated it bad).[54] The mean response on the 1-9 scale was 7.5
for ethicists, 7.4 for non-ethicist philosophers, and 7.1 for non-philosophers.[55] In response to the question about how much
the typical professor should donate, only 9% of ethicists entered “0”, compared
to 24% of non-ethicist philosophers and 25% of non-philosophers.[56] Among the non-zeros, ethicists’ log-transformed
mean answer was 5.9% of income, compared to 4.8% for the other two groups.[57]
Non-ethicist philosophers reported having donated the
least to charity in 2008. 10% reported
having donated nothing, compared to 4% of ethicists and 6% of non-philosophers. Excluding the 0’s, non-ethicist philosophers’
(log-transformed) mean self-reported donation rate was 2.6%, compared to 3.7%
for ethicists and 3.6% for non-philosophers.[58]
However, in our one direct measure of charitable
behavior, non-ethicist philosophers behaved the most charitably. Only non-ethicist philosophers showed a
significantly higher response rate to the charity version of our study than to
the non-charity version: 67% responsiveness with the charity incentive vs. 59%
without. For non-philosophers the spread
was 55% vs. 52%. Ethicists showed no
difference whatsoever, 59% for both versions.[59]
These small differentials in response rate suggest
either that the charity incentive was almost entirely unmotivating or,
alternatively, that it led some respondents to reconceptualize responsiveness
as warranted only if the incentive seemed worth it, weakening whatever prior motivations
they may have had. (For what it’s worth,
$10 for 10 minutes of work would translate to an annual rate of $120,000 a year
at 40 hours per week for 50 weeks, well over professors’ median salary of about
$80,000 in 2009.) These hypotheses can to
some extent be distinguished by examining responses to the charity questions in
the survey. Suppose that offering the
charity incentive led recipients of the charity version of the survey to
conceptualize responsiveness as quid-pro-quo and thus led them to respond not
from the motives that generate responsiveness to the unincentivized version of
the survey but rather only if $10 to charity for ten minutes’ time seemed to
them a good deal. If that were the case,
then we should expect psychological differences between respondents to the two versions
of the survey: Respondents to the charity version should be those among the
charity-version recipient pool who value charity relatively highly (finding the
quo worth the quid), while respondents to the non-charity version should have a
broader and more representative spread of attitudes toward charity (i.e., lower
overall). This prediction is not born
out. Respondents to the charity version
trended only slightly, and not statistically significantly, toward higher mean
moral ratings regarding donating 10% of one’s income to charity: 7.4, compared
to 7.3 for respondents to the version without the charity incentive; and both
groups of respondents reported having donated about the same amount to charity
in 2008, (log-transformed) mean 3.3% vs. 3.2%, again well within statistical
chance.[60] This lack of difference in responses to the
two versions, combined with the tiny difference in overall response rates, thus
suggests that recipients were generally little moved by the charity
incentive. On the bright side, it also
suggests a certain amount of stability
in response: Respondents’ answers to our charity questions don’t appear to have
been much influenced by the presence or absence of the charity incentive.
Non-philosophers showed the strongest relationship
between expressed normative attitude about how much the typical professor
should give and how much they themselves reported giving in 2008, and ethicists
showed the weakest attitude-behavior relationship: The correlation was .62 for
non-philosophers, .46 for non-ethicist philosophers, and .33 for ethicists.[61] However, there was no correlation whatsoever
between expressed normative view on the nine-point scale and self-reported
charitable donation in 2008 (r = -.07 or .00, depending on calculation method).[62]
In sum, ethicists expressed the strongest normative attitudes
in favor of charitable donation.
However, ethicists and non-philosophers reported having donated about
the same amount of income in 2008.
Although non-ethicist philosophers reported lower rates of charitable
donation in 2008 than did the other two groups, in our one direct measure of
behavior – responsiveness to the charity incentive included with half the
surveys – it was only the non-ethicist philosophers who appeared motivated to
behave charitably. Ethicists showed the
weakest relationship between expressed normative view and self-reported
behavior, non-philosophers the strongest.
11. Survey Response Honesty.
Although the charity questions were the final
questions in Part I of the survey, we added one more normative question near
the end of the survey. Question 24 was
“Using the same scale as in the first part of this questionnaire, please
indicate the degree to which reporting dishonestly to survey questions such as
the ones presented here is morally good or morally bad”. This question was followed by the usual 1-9
scale. We then asked:
25. Were you
dishonest in any of your answers to previous questions?
¨ yes
¨ no
¨ don’t recall
This
concluded Part II of the survey. We also
directly measured survey honesty or accuracy by combining several measures of
suspicious responding, described below.
The groups did not appear to differ in normative view,
with 89% of ethicists rating survey dishonesty on the bad side of the scale,
compared to 87% of non-ethicist philosophers and 86% of non-philosophers.[63] Very few respondents self-reported
dishonesty: 2% of ethicists, 4% of non-ethicist philosophers, and 2% of
non-philosophers (not a statistically detectable difference).[64] In the comments field, several respondents
indicated surprise that we would ask explicitly for reports of survey
dishonesty, but since we were also measuring honesty or accuracy directly we
thought it best to give respondents a chance to self-report it.
The most straightforward measure of honesty or accuracy
was a comparison of self-reported APA membership with presence on the
membership list, discussed in Section 4 above.
As mentioned there, we found a weak trend for ethicists to be more likely
to overreport membership than non-ethicists.
In contrast, non-philosophers trended toward being most likely to have
demonstrably overreported voting, though the numbers were small.[65] For the other questions, suspicious
responding had to be statistically inferred (see note 66 for details), but on
no measure did we find a significant difference between the groups.
As a final comparison, we aggregated suspicious
responding across all measures, awarding respondents one point for each
suspicious response.[66] We did this only for philosophers, due to
denominator differences in society membership honesty and reported meat meals
per week. Ethicists did not differ from
non-ethicist philosophers by this measure: 56% of both groups gave at least one
suspicious response – which, we emphasize, is quite consistent with actual
scrupulous honesty for any individual survey respondent – and 15% of both
groups gave two or more suspicious responses.[67]
Somewhat oddly, perhaps, philosophers who gave at
least two suspicious responses rated survey dishonesty morally worse on our 1-9
scale than did philosophers who gave at most one suspicious response: mean 2.8
vs. 3.2 for ethicists, 2.9 vs. 3.5 for non-ethicists.[68] Non-philosophers showed no such difference,
trending instead toward attitude-behavior consistency.[69]
In sum, the rate of survey dishonesty, or bias toward
socially desirable responding, appears to be about the same for all three
groups, though philosophers showed a negative relationship between expressed
attitude and measured behavior.
12. Summary Statistics of Moral Behavior.
Overall, there appears to be no trend toward ethicists
behaving better across measures. To
confirm this more formally we created three summary statistics of measured and
self-reported moral behavior. We are
cautious about the value of such summary statistics and certainly do not regard
them as valid overall indices of people’s moral character. However, aggregating our data across the
several measures offers the chance to pick up small but consistent trends that
might not show statistically in the measures considered individually.
Our first summary statistic gave recipients one point
each for behavior in accord with the normative view of the majority of philosophy
respondents, using one cross-group measure of each type of behavior. Specifically, we awarded one point for
self-reported societal membership, one point for self-reported voting frequency
of at least once per year, one point for reporting contact with one’s mother
once per month or more, one point for reporting not having eaten mammal meat at
the previous evening meal, one point for being an organ donor, one point for
reporting having donated blood since 2005, and one point for responding to at
least half of the emails we sent.[70] Out of seven possible points, then, the mean
was 4.4 for ethicists, 4.3 for non-ethicist philosophers, and 4.5 for
non-philosophers – well within statistical chance.[71] All the groups also showed the same variance
in scores, contrary to what one might predict if one thought (as we have
sometimes heard) that even if ethicists behave on average the same as
non-ethicists, they split bimodally into those who behave substantially better
than average and those who behave substantially worse.[72]
A second summary statistic, limited to philosophers,
adds in one more possible point for giving no suspicious survey responses and
substitutes measured APA membership for self-reported membership. This statistic finds, again, similar totals
for ethicists and other philosophers, ethicists with a mean score of 4.7 out of
8 and other philosophers with a mean of 4.6.[73]
A third statistic modifies the first by excluding the
two most controversial behaviors: societal membership and vegetarianism. The means for this statistic were also within
chance, though there was a statistically marginal spread between the groups,
with ethicists in the middle: 3.0, 2.8, and 3.1 respectively (out of 5).[74]
Across the measures, however, it does seem that
ethicists were the most moralizing – that is, the least likely to describe the
nine behaviors as morally neutral.
Ethicists rated as “morally neutral” an average of 1.8 of the nine
scaled normative questions in Part I, compared to an average of 2.1 for
non-ethicist philosophers and 2.7 for non-philosophers.[75]
The difference is significant even if
the vegetarianism question is excluded: 1.4 vs. 1.5 vs. 1.9.[76]
Finally, we aggregated our measures of the attitude-behavior
relationship by combining correlation scores across the measures using the
tools of statistical meta-analysis (Rosenthal and Rosnow 1984/2008). The differences were well within chance: Using
qualitative measures of normative attitude (good vs. not good or bad vs. not
bad), the aggregated attitude-behavior correlation was .16 for ethicists and
.15 for the other two groups. Using the
1-9 scale of normative attitude, the aggregated attitude-behavior correlation was
.20 for ethicists, .24 for non-ethicist philosophers, and .16 for
non-philosophers.[77]
13. Age and Gender.
We had gender information for most survey recipients,
either discovered in voter registration records or inferred from name and
photograph on their academic website; and for about half we had birth year
information from voter registration records.
We had been concerned about gender and age as potential confounds,
especially gender, given that women are underrepresented among philosophers
compared to their representation in academia as a whole and given recent work
suggesting that they often have different philosophical views (Buckwalter and
Stich 2010).
Among survey recipients for whom we had birth year
information, there was no statistically detectable age difference among the
groups.[78] Respondents trended toward being younger than
non-respondents (mean birth year 1955 vs. 1953), though this difference did not
achieve statistical significance.[79] Age confounds thus seem unlikely to be
playing much of a role in survey responses.
Only in two respects did older respondents detectably differ in their
survey responses or measured behavior: They were less likely to endorse
vegetarianism and they voted more frequently.[80]
Women were more likely to respond to the survey than
were men (65% vs. 57%), and they were less likely to be philosophers,
especially non-ethicist philosophers (28% of ethicists were women, 17% of
non-ethicist philosophers, and 35% of non-philosophers).[81] Thus, gender could potentially have played a
confounding role. Fortunately, however,
the only issue on which we found statistically significant gender differences
was vegetarianism.[82] Among female respondents, 55% rated eating
meat as bad, compared to 37% of men.[83] Since women were less likely to be
philosophers, this gender difference is even more evident when respondents are
divided by group: The gender split was 78%-50% among ethicists, 70%-39% among
non-ethicist philosophers, and 24%-14% among non-philosophers.[84] Women also reported eating much less meat: In
each analysis group, women reported eating about half as many meat meals per
week as men: 2.6 vs. 4.9 for ethicists, 2.5 vs. 5.1 for non-ethicist
philosophers, and 3.9 vs. 6.4 for non-philosophers.[85] The splits by last evening meal were not
quite as large, however: 27% vs. 44% for ethicists, 32% vs. 33% for
non-ethicist philosophers, 39% vs. 51% for non-philosophers.[86]
Thus, the normative question about vegetarianism
showed large differences by group, gender, and age. These factors combined to generate very large
cumulative differences: Altogether, 81% of female philosophy respondents born
1960 or later rated eating the meat of mammals as morally bad, compared to 7%
of male non-philosophers born before 1960.[87] However, this huge difference in expressed
normative attitude does not appear to be accompanied by a correspondingly large
shift in actual behavior. Women and
philosophers, as described above, were only marginally less likely to report
having eaten meat at their previous evening meal; and by age trend was even
weaker, with an average birth year of 1954 for those reporting having eaten
meat at the previous evening meal and 1955 for those reporting not having
eating meat at the previous evening meal.[88] Among female philosophers born 1960 or later,
38% reported having eaten meat at the previous evening meal – compared to 37%
for all remaining respondents combined.[89]
13. Abstractness of Ethical Interest and
Normative Ethical Theory.
In informal conversation, philosophers have often
suggested to us that metaethicists – who study the most abstract questions
about the nature of moral norms, such as whether there are moral truths at all
– behave on average worse than do normative ethicists (who study particular
broad normative theories like conseqeuentialism, deontology, or virtue ethics)
and applied ethicists (who study issues like abortion, environmentalism, animal
rights, or global poverty). Others have
suggested that applied ethicists behave morally better than do the other two
groups. Also in informal conversation,
many philosophers have suggested to us that deontologists (who hold, roughly,
that to be moral is to follow a certain set of rules) tend to behave morally
worse than consequentialists (who hold, roughly, that morality is about
producing good consequences) and/or virtue ethicists (who hold, roughly, that
to be moral is to possess a suite of virtues like kindness and courage). Our empirical data support none of these
contentions.
Philosophy recipients received two questions, set
aside in Part III, that we did not pose to non-philosophy recipients.
26. If an
ethics-related area is among your specializations which of the following best
reflects the level of abstraction at which you tend to consider ethical
issues? (check all that apply)
¨ metaethics
¨ normative ethics
¨ applied ethics
¨ no ethics-related area
among my specializations
27. What
normative ethical view do you find broadly most appealing? (check one)
¨ deontological
¨ consequentialist
¨ virtue ethical
¨ skeptical
¨ no settled position
Among
ethicist respondents, 35% expressed a focus in metaethics, 64% in normative
ethics, and 47% in applied ethics (these categories obviously overlapping). Among philosopher respondents as a whole, 23%
reported attraction to deontology, 14% to consequentialism, 29% to virtue
ethics, and 4% to skepticism, while 31% reported no settled position.[90]
We detected no statistically significant differences
in either expressed moral attitude or moral behavior among ethicists who pursue
their trade at different levels of abstraction.
However, due to the relatively small sample size, our power to
statistically detect differences in moral behavior is somewhat limited.[91]
Looking at our data by normative ethical view –
including only philosophers who selected either deontology, consequentialism,
or virtue ethics from our list – we found virtue ethicists tending to express
more neutral moral views on APA membership, organ donation, and blood donation.[92] Consonantly, they were least likely to report
being organ donors and marginally least likely to belong to the APA.[93] There were no other detectable differences by
normative theory. Despite the
association of vegetarianism with consequentialism (e.g., Singer 1975/2002), we
did not find consequentialists any more likely to rate eating meat as bad or
any less likely to report having eating meat at the previous evening meal.[94]
14. Conclusion.
The four simple models offered in the introduction
made different predictions about the data, given the background framing
assumptions. We will now compare the
predictions with the results. Given the
complexity of human behavior and the imperfections in our measures, we will not
hold it against a model if a few results run contrary to its predictions, as
long as the contrary results appear to be outliers from a general trend.
The booster model predicts that ethicists will show
the best moral behavior, the truest moral attitudes, and the strongest attitude-behavior
relationship, on the assumption that they tend to engage in more philosophical
moral reflection than do the comparison groups and are otherwise socially
similar in dimensions relevant to the moral behavior under investigation. This model, we think, is very difficult to
sustain in light of our data on moral behavior.
We now have a number of direct measures of moral behavior. In previous research, we have found
ethicists, including political philosophers, to vote at about the same rate as
other professors (Schwitzgebel and Rust 2010), to reply emails apparently
written by students at about the same rate as other professors (Rust and
Schwitzgebel in preparation), to behave about as courteously at philosophy
conferences (though environmental ethicists did appear to litter less;
Schwitzgebel, Rust, Huang, Moore, and Coates forthcoming), to be rated morally about
the same overall by their peers (Schwitzgebel and Rust 2009), and to
misappropriate library books no less often (perhaps more often, Schwitzgebel
2009). In the current research, we found
ethicists about as likely to pay membership dues to the APA, to be about as
accurate or honest in their survey responses, and to be no more responsive than
the other groups to the charity incentive (perhaps less responsive). Turning to self-report measures, all groups
reported similarly high rates of having an organ donor symbol on their driver’s
license and similarly low rates of blood donation. Non-philosophers reported keeping best in
contact with their mothers; non-philosophers and ethicists reported similar
overall rates of charitable donation, somewhat higher than non-philosophers’;
and non-philosophers were marginally most likely to report having eating meat
at the previous evening meal. We regard
these results as an approximate tie among the groups – as is also suggested by
our three summary measures.
The remaining three models all predict that ethicists
will behave about the same as otherwise socially similar non-ethicists (except
for the toxic rationalization sub-model, which predicts worse behavior). In this respect, all three models match the
majority of the data described above.
However, the three models make different predictions about normative
attitudes and attitude-behavior consistency.
The epiphenomenal model predicts no differences in
attitude or attitude-behavior consistency.
This model stands somewhat in tension with our data, but perhaps not
irreconcilably. Ethicists’ attitudes
were similar to non-ethicists’ on the majority of issues; but on several issues
– organ and blood donation, charitable donation, and especially vegetarianism –
they exhibited more demanding moral views than did the other groups. This is a consistent enough tendency for us
to think there is something to it: Ethicists’ moral views are not identical to
those of non-ethicists, perhaps tending toward the more demanding. Of course this claim, if true, says nothing
about causal direction or the role of philosophical moral reflection in
generating such views. A revised epiphenomenalism
might attribute these differences in moral view to antecedent differences
between the types of people who enter ethics vs. other areas of academia,
differences arising from causes other than philosophical moral reflection (thus
rejecting one of our framing background assumptions). The epiphenomenalist model similarly only
partly fits with our data on attitude-behavior consistency. Although on the majority of measures all
groups showed similarly low-to-moderate relationships between expressed
normative attitude and measured or self-reported behavior (and they also showed
very similar attitude-behavior relationships in our two aggregate measures),
there were significant between-group differences in attitude-behavior
consistency on four of the normative issues under investigation: Ethicists
showed the strongest attitude-behavior relationship on the issue of voting,
non-ethicist philosophers showed the strongest relationship on the issues of
organ donation and staying in contact with one’s mother, and non-ethicists
showed the strongest relationship on the issue of charitable donation. We see no unified interpretation of these
results; probably multiple factors are at work (including possibly shortcomings
in the survey that play out differently for the different groups).
The inert rationalization model predicts no
differences in moral behavior (thus, “inert” rationalization, as opposed to
“toxic”), but it does predict that ethicists will show a stronger attitude-behavior
relationship due to an increased tendency to rationalize their behavior post-hoc
by adopting self-flattering normative attitudes. Although the moral behavior data fit fairly
well with this model, as noted above, the majority of our data on the attitude-behavior
relationship do not. Nonetheless, it’s
perhaps worth noting that the voting data fit the inert rationalization model
beautifully: Ethicists voting participation is virtually identical to other
groups’, both in mean and in variance, but ethicists show a substantially
stronger relationship between behavior and attitude than do the other groups. The simplest interpretation of this pattern
of results is inert rationalization: Professors’ voting behavior is determined by
factors having nothing to do with philosophical reflection and is thus the same
among all the groups (given that they are adequately matched in other respects);
philosophical moral reflection serves only to shift respondent’s attitudes into
line with those pre-existing behavioral tendencies, ethicists showing the
greatest attitudinal shift (and thus the highest correlation between attitude
and behavior) and non-philosophers showing the smallest shift.
The motivationally ineffectual discovery model predicts
that ethicists and non-ethicists will behave similarly, that ethicists will have
normative views closer to the truth, and that ethicists will probably show
lower norm-behavior consistency (to the extent that discovering moral truths
frees them from self-serving rationalizations that artificially inflate
attitude-behavior consistency in non-ethicists). The data summarized above mostly confirm the
prediction about moral behavior and mostly disconfirm the prediction about attitude-behavior
consistency, except on the issue of charitable donation. Whether ethicists also have normative views
closer to the truth we can conditionally assess. Ethicists were more likely than the other
groups to praise blood donation, to demand relatively high rates of charitable
donation, and to condemn meat eating and not having an organ donation
symbol. If these attitudes are closer to the moral truth, then that speaks
in favor of this aspect of the motivationally ineffectual discovery model.
We are inclined toward a hybrid view according to which
the psychological story is complicated.
No simple view fits our data very well, and given the many limitations
of our studies – including the background assumption that ethicists are similar
to the comparison groups in all relevant dimensions apart from a greater
tendency toward philosophical moral reflection – we think it premature to draw
strong conclusions. We do think it is
probably warranted at this point, however, pending further evidence, to reject
the view that ethicists behave, on average, morally better than do
non-ethicists. This result appears to
leave us with three broad options, each empirically explorable with further
research: (1.) Philosophical reflection simply has no influence on moral
behavior. (2.) Philosophical reflection
has both positive and negative effects on moral behavior (maybe the booster is
sometimes right and the toxic rationalization view sometimes right),
approximately cancelling out on average.
Or (3.) One of the background assumptions of our research is false:
Perhaps (3a.) ethicists would tend to behave morally worse than non-ethicists
except that their philosophical moral reflection works to bring them up to
average (e.g., maybe they tend to have deficient moral emotional reactions that
they compensate for intellectually), or perhaps (3b.) ethicists in fact are no
more likely to engage in philosophical moral reflection on issues related to
their outward behavior than are socially similar non-ethicists. A next step would be to test 3a and 3b and to
try to pry apart 1 from 2.
A priori and phenomenologically, we do not find Option
1 very attractive. However, empirically,
it seems very much in play. It remains
to be shown that even a lifetime’s worth of philosophical moral reflection has
any influence upon one’s real-world moral behavior.[95]
References
Aristotle (4th
c. BCE/1962). Nicomachean Ethics. Trans.
M. Ostwald.
Baier, Annette (1985). Postures of the Mind. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota.
Bernstein, Robert, Anita Chadha,
and Robert Mountjoy (2001).
Overreporting voting: Why it happens and why it matters. Public
Opinion Quarterly, 65, 22-44.
Buckwalter, Wesley, and
Stephen Stich (2010). Gender and philosophical
intuition. Unpublished manuscript.
Hadot, Pierre (1995). Philosophy
as a Way of Life. Trans. A.
Davidson. Malden, MA: Blackwell.
Holbrook, Allyson L., and
Jon A. Krosnick (2010). Social
desirability bias in voter turnout reports: Tests using the item count
technique. Public Opinion Quarterly, 74, 37-67.
Ivanhoe, Philip J.
(1993/2000). Confucian Moral Self-Cultivation, 2nd ed. Indianapolis: Hackett.
Kant, Immanuel (1785/2002). Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals. Trans. A. Zweig. Ed. T.E. Hill & A. Zweig. Oxford: Oxford.
Knobe, Joshua, and Brian Leiter (2007). The case for Nietzschean moral psychology. In B. Leiter & N. Sinhababu (eds.), Nietzsche and Morality. Oxford: Oxford.
Mill, John Stuart
(1859/2003). On Liberty. In M. Warnock
(ed.), Utilitarianism and On
Moeller, Hans-Georg (2009). The
Moral Fool. New York: Columbia.
Posner, Richard A. (1999). The Problematics of Moral and Legal Theory. Cambridge, MA: Harvard.
Rosenthal, Robert, and Ralph
L. Rosnow (1984/2008). Essentials of Behavioral Research, 3rd
ed. Boston: McGraw Hill.
Rust, Joshua, and Eric
Schwitzgebel (in preparation). Ethicists’
and non-ethicists’ responsiveness to student emails: Relationships among expressed
normative attitude, self-described behavior, and experimentally observed behavior.
Schwitzgebel, Eric (2009). Do ethicists steal more books? Philosophical
Psychology, 22, 711-725.
Schwitzgebel, Eric, and
Joshua Rust (2009). The moral behaviour
of ethicists: Peer opinion. Mind, 118, 1043-1059.
Schwitzgebel, Eric, and Joshua
Rust (2010). Do ethicists and political philosophers
vote more often than other professors? Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 1, 189-199.
Schwitzgebel, Eric, Joshua
Rust, Linus T. Huang, Alan Moore, and Justin Coates (forthcoming). Ethicists’ courtesy at philosophy conferences. Philosophical
Psychology.
Singer, Peter (1972). Famine, affluence, and morality. Philosophy
and Public Affairs, 1, 229-243.
Singer, Peter (1975/2002). Animal
Liberation, 3rd ed. New
York: HarperCollins.
Williams, Bernard (1985). Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard.
[1]
These numbers exclude 17 ethicists, 33 non-ethicist philosophers, and 44
non-philosophers from the targeted universities for whom we could not obtain
valid email or postal addresses or who knew too much about our hypotheses to be
useful respondents.
[2]
Overall, only 25 respondents (4%) dropped out of the survey, completing the
first question but reaching a point after which they completed no more
questions. Most questions had response
rates in the high 90-percents, typically 98%-100% excluding dropouts.
[3]
Philosophers 70% vs. non-philosophers 92%, χ2 = 31.2, p <
.001. Ethicists 74% vs. non-ethicist
philosophers 65%, χ2 = 3.8, p = .052. Unless otherwise specified, we employ an alpha
level of .05 for statistical significance and .10 for statistical marginality.
[4]
χ2 = 0.9, p = .63 (collapsing neutral and bad).
[5]
The difference in mean rating is statistically significant by ANOVA (F = 5.2, p
= .006), but given the scaling issues mentioned in Section 3, we don’t regard
differences of less than 0.5 on the nine-point scale as meaningful – at least
when the non-philosophers’ means are farthest from center.
[6]
χ2 = 5.6, p = .06; merging the two philosophy groups, χ2
= 5.6, p = .02; excluding 3 respondents answering “don’t recall”.
[7]
χ2 = 0.3, p = .56. Also,
6% of respondents underreported membership, perhaps some of which were emeritus
members no longer paying dues but still entitled to appear on the membership
list.
[8]
χ2 = 18.7, p < .001; ethicists 67% vs. 54%, χ2
= 6.0, p = .01; non-ethicist philosophers 69% vs. 49%, χ2 =
13.6, p < .001.
[9]
Ethicists: χ2 = 11.1, p = .001 (for self-reported membership,
χ2 = 9.7, p = .002); non-ethicist philosophers: χ2
= 3.0, p = .09 (for self-reported membership, χ2 = 2.0, p =
.15).
[10]
We compare strength of attitude-behavior relationship by converting the
two-by-two tables to correlations, then using Fisher’s zr conversion
to test for differences in effect size (Rosenthal and Rosnow 1984/2008): ethicists
r = .24 vs. non-ethicist philosophers r = .12, p = .22.
[11]
χ2 = 2.4, p = .30 (collapsing neutral and bad).
[12]
ANOVA, F = 16.0, p < .001. Tukey
pairwise comparisons find non-philosophers different from both ethicists and
non-ethicist philosophers but finds no difference between ethicists and
non-ethicist philosophers.
[13]
χ2 = 8.2, p = .02. All
but four respondents who reported zero votes also reported being ineligible to
vote in the U.S. In Schwitzgebel and
Rust 2010 we report evidence from academic homepages that also suggests lower
citizenship rates among non-ethicist philosophers.
[14]
ANOVA, F = 0.7, p = .51. All vote rate
data is square-root transformed for a better approximation to normality.
[15]ANOVA,
F = 0.3, p = .76, excluding recipients whose first state-recorded vote was in
2008 and recipients without a good name match in the voter rolls (see
Schwitzgebel and Rust 2010 for methodological details).
[16]
SD .22 for ethicists, .22 for
non-ethicist philosophers, and .21 for non-philosophers (Bartlett’s test for
equal variances, p = .49).
[17]
T-test, t = 3.9, p < .001. The
non-philosophers had the lowest response rates and correspondingly the largest
non-response bias in voting rates: 1.20 vs. 1.01 (T-test, t = 2.9, p = .005).
[18]
U.S. participation rates from http://elections.gmu.edu/Turnout_2008G.html
(accessed March 1, 2011). Only three
ethicists, five non-ethicist philosophers, and two non-philosophers appeared to
falsely report voting in the 2008 U.S. general election; Fisher’s exact test, p
= .62.
[19]
Paired-t, t = -3.1, p = .003. Only 88
respondents had full voting records since the year 2000, which required our
having antecedently found an unambiguous name match in the states’ voter
database, that voter’s continuous registration in that state since the year
2000, and complete state records for that voter since the year 2000 (this last
criterion excluded all California respondents, since California did not provide
data for local elections). Eight of the
30 ethicists for whom we had full voting records since the year 2000
overreported voting (27%), compared to seven of 24 non-ethicist philosophers
(29%) and 15 of 34 non-philosophers (44%); given the small numbers involved
this difference does not approach statistical significance (χ2
= 2.5, p = .28).
[20]
ANOVA, F = 0.1, p = .93.
[21]t
= 0.8, p = .42.
[22]
Pearson’s r; p < .001, .18, and .91 respectively; merging all groups, r =
.18, p = .003. Correlations compared
using Fisher’s zr conversion: ethicists vs. non-ethicist philosophers,
p = .08 (marg. sig. two-tailed); ethicists vs. non-philosophers, p = .01.
[23]
χ2 = 0.5, p = .79 (collapsing neutral and good).
[24]
These means are statistically different (ANOVA, F = 4.3, p = .01), but due to
the scaling concerns discussed above we do not interpret differences of less
than 0.5 on the scale as meaningful when non-philosophers’ means are the
farthest from center.
[25]
χ2 = 5.6, p = .06 (marg. sig.); χ2 = 8.0, p =
.02.
[26]
χ2 = 0.4, p = .82.
[27]
ANOVA, F = 1.2, p = .31. Log-transformed
mean: emean(ln(xi)).
[28]
ANOVAs, F ≤ 1.5, p ≥ .24.
[29]
χ2 = 20.5, p < .001, excluding respondents reporting
deceased mothers.
[30]
Respectively, χ2 = 0.9, p = .35; χ2 = 4.1, p =
.04.
[31]
Pearson’s r, ln(x+1)-tranformed, p < .001, .17, and .37 respectively;
merging all groups, r = .26, p < .001.
Correlations compared using Fisher’s zr conversion:
non-ethicist philosophers vs. ethicists, p = .008; non-ethicist philosophers
vs. non-philosophers, p = .004. The
differences are more subtle, and not statistically significant, using the
vaguer and presumably less valid (though higher N) measure of self-reported
rate of monthly contact.
[32]
χ2 = 64.2, p < .001 (collapsing neutral and good).
[33]
ANOVA, F = 17.0, p < .001, Tukey pairwise comparisons finding both
philosopher groups different from the non-philosophers but not from each other.
[34]
χ2 = 5.7, p = .06, excluding two respondents who stated that
they didn’t recall; comparing just ethicists vs. non-philosophers, χ2
= 2.4, p = .12.
[35]
ANOVA (square-root transformed), F = 5.2, p = .006, reducing one response from
“500” (marginal comment “Bacon tastes good”) to 25.
[36]
χ2 = 9.3, p = .01. Only
one respondent, an ethicist, reported between zero and one meals per week (.5,
classified as non-vegetarian).
[37]
χ2 = 0.0, p = .98.
[38]
Bad vs. not bad: overall χ2 = 24.5, p < .001; ethicists
χ2 = 12.0, p = .001; non-ethicist philosophers χ2
= 1.6, p = .20 (but note that a one-tailed p-value might be more appropriate
for this test); non-philosophers χ2 = 8.1, p = .005; effect
size comparison using Fisher’s zr conversion: r values .26, .09,
.22; pairwise, the ethicists vs. non-ethicist philosophers difference was marginally
significant, p = .09. 1-9 scale: overall
Pearson’s r = .24, p < .001; ethicists r = .28, non-ethicist philosophers r
= .17, non-philosophers r = .24 (group p’s ≤ .02, effect sizes not
significantly different).
[39]
χ2 = 8.7, p = .01 (collapsing neutral and bad); χ2
= 13.2, p = .001 (collapsing neutral and good).
5% of respondents rated donating blood as bad and 2% rated not having a
donor symbol as good. ANOVA finds
differences in mean response for the organ question (ethicists mean 4.0 vs.
non-ethicist philosophers 4.1 vs. non-philosophers 4.4, F = 5.5, p = .004) but
not the blood question (6.8 vs. 6.7 vs. 6.9, F = 0.4, p = .65).
[40]
χ2 = 0.6, p = .75.
[41]
χ2 = 0.8, p = .67.
[42]
The last two comparisons are statistically significant by the one-sample t-test:
t = 4.7, p < .001; t = 2.0, p = .046.
[43]
Among non-ethicist philosophers, 82% of those who rated it as bad not to have a
donor symbol reported having a donor symbol, compared to 44% who rated it as
neutral or good. The split was 79% vs.
53% for non-ethicist philosophers and 81% vs. 60% for non-philosophers; χ2
= 13.2, p < .001; χ2 = 31.7, p < .001; χ2
= 7.5, p = .006. Effect size comparison
using Fisher’s zr conversion: r values .27, .41, .22; pairwise,
non-ethicist philosophers vs. non-philosophers p = .048, non-ethicist
philosophers vs. ethicists p = .13. T-tests comparing mean normative view between
donors and non-donors yield similar results with greater statistical
significance for the effect size comparison: non-ethicists philosophers mean
3.8 vs. 4.6 (t = 6.5, p < .001) compared to 3.8 vs. 4.4 for ethicists (t =
4.0, p < .001) and 4.3 vs. 4.6 for non-philosophers (t = 1.4, p = .15);
effect size comparison using Fisher’s zr conversion, non-ethicist
philosophers vs. ethicists p = .13, vs. non-philosophers .005. 16% of ethicists who rated blood donation as
good reported donating in 2008 or 2009, vs. 0% of ethicists who did not rate
blood donation as good; the split was 16% vs. 4% for non-ethicist philosophers
and 14% vs. 0% for non-philosophers; overall χ2 = 10.7, p =
.001; by group, ethicists χ2 = 3.6, p = .06; non-ethicist
philosophers χ2 = 2.3, p = .13; non-philosophers χ2
= 4.8, p = .03. Among eligible
ethicists, 36% of those who rated blood donation as good reported donating at
least once every few years, compared to 15% who rated it as neutral or bad
(χ2 = 3.3, p = .07); the split was 36% vs. 21% for non-ethicist
philosophers (χ2 = 2.1, p = .15) and 47% vs. 10% for
non-philosophers (χ2 = 12.6, p < .001). Pairwise Fisher zr conversion
correlation comparison finds a marginally significant trend toward a larger
attitude-behavior relationship among the non-philosophers than the non-ethicist
philosophers (r = .36 vs. .13, p = .09); however as usual we treat the
generalization question more cautiously than the specific instance question. T-tests comparing mean normative rating
depending on self-reported donation at least once every few years (excluding
ineligible) show similar results: ethicists mean 7.4 vs. 6.7 (t = 2.4, p =
.02); non-ethicist philosophers 6.9 vs. 6.6 (t = 1.1, p = .27); non-philosophers
7.4 vs. 6.5 (t = 3.4, p = .001); effect size comparison using Fisher’s zr
conversion, non-philosophers vs. non-ethicist philosophers r = .30 vs. .10, p =
.12.
[44]
χ2 = 0.4 (collapsing neutral and good), p = .83. Although the means are statistically different
(ANOVA, F = 5.2, p = .006), because of the scaling issues discussed above we do
not interpret differences of less than 0.5 points as meaningful when
non-philosophers are in the most extreme group.
[45]
Among respondents, 97 ethicists, 110 non-ethicist philosophers, and 94
non-philosophers received all three emails.
ANOVA, F = 0.9, p = .43.
[46]
First email: 63% for each group (χ2 = 0.0, p = .99). Second email: 61% for ethicists, 55% for
non-ethicist philosophers, 56% for non-philosophers (χ2 = 1.0,
p = .60). Third email: 69% vs. 62% vs.
66% (χ2 = 2.0, p = .38).
Although the trend favored ethicists on emails 2 and 3, this trend did
not approach statistical significance even on an expanded sample (see Rust and
Schwitzgebel in preparation).
[47]
t = -2.8, p = .006 (215 non-respondents vs. 301 respondents).
[48]
χ2 = 2.0, p = .37; χ2 = 1.7, p = .42.
[49]
Pearson’s r, p = .001, with self-reported responsiveness transformed by
-(log(101-x)).
[50]
Pearson’s r, p values of .001, .08, and .37 respectively. Effect size comparison by Fisher’s zr
conversion finds non-philosophers vs. non-ethicist philosophers marginally
significant at p = .06.
[51]
χ2 = 0.3, p = .88.
[52]
Merged groups, t = 0.5, p = .60; ethicists t = 0.6, p = .54; non-ethicist
philosophers t = -0.8, p = .40; non-philosophers t = 1.3, p = .21.
[53]
Pearson’s r, overall, p < .001; by group, p < .001, p = .001, p = .099,
respectively; effect size comparison by Fisher’s zr conversion,
ethicists vs. non-philosophers p = .01, ethicists vs. non-ethicist philosophers
p = .13.
[54]
χ2 = 17.0, p < .001 (collapsing neutral and bad). One respondent who rated donating 10% bad
said that the typical professor should donate 15% and thus appears to have
rated 10% bad because 10% is too little.
[55]
ANOVA, F = 4.3, p = .01, Tukey pairwise comparisons finding ethicists higher
than non-philosophers. Although the
difference in means is not large, it is in the direction opposite of that
predicted by the apparent scaling differences so we interpret it as meaningful.
[56]
χ2 = 18.2, p < .001 (rounding to zero one ethicist’s
response of .001%).
[57]
ANOVA, F = 3.6, p = .03, Tukey pairwise comparisons only marginally
significant.
[58]
On the zeros: χ2 = 5.9, p = .052 (again rounding to zero one
ethicist’s response of .001%). On the
mean: ANOVA, F = 5.5, p = .004, Tukey pairwise comparisons finding significant
differences between non-ethicist philosophers and both other groups. Variance in charitable donation was similar
among the groups: log-transformed SD for all groups 1.0, Bartlett’s test, p =
.87. The zeros and percentages can
reasonably be merged using a square-root transform (excluding one outlying
non-ethicist philosopher who reported donating 500% of 2008 income): ANOVA, F =
10.4, p < .001, Tukey pairwise finding significant differences between the
non-ethicist philosophers and both other groups.
[59]
Non-ethicists χ2 = 2.8, p = .097, a one-tailed p value of .049;
non-philosophers χ2 = 0.2, p = .64; ethicists χ2
= 0.0, p = 1.0.
[60]
t = 0.9, p = .36; t = 0.2, p = .83.
[61]
Pearson’s r, all p’s < .001 (log-transformed and excluding 0’s); effect-size
comparison by Fisher’s zr conversion, ethicists vs. non-philosophers
p < .001, ethicists vs. non-ethicist philosophers p = .20, non-ethicist
philosophers vs. non-philosophers p = .06.
The Pearson correlations, square-root transformed and including the 0’s
(but excluding the outlier) are .24 for ethicists, .41 for non-ethicist
philosophers, and .51 for non-philosophers.
[62]
Log-transformed Pearson’s correlation (excluding zeros) -.07, p = .13;
non-log-transformed correlation (including zeros but excluding one outlier)
exactly .00, p = 1.00.
[63]
χ2 = 0.6, p = .74 (collapsing neutral and good; 3% rated
dishonesty as good). Means 3.2, 3.4, and
2.9; ANOVA, F = 7.0, p = .001, but as usual we don’t interpret as meaningful
the slightly more extreme mean of the non-philosophers, given scaling concerns.
[64]
Fisher’s exact test, p = .47.
[65]
See note 19.
[66]
One suspicious response point was awarded for overreporting APA membership; for
demonstrably overreporting voting, either in 2008 or overall; for reporting maternal
contact once a month and not within 30 days, 2-4 times a month and not within
15 days, 5 times a month and not within 10 days; for reporting 3 or fewer meat
meals per week and meat the previous night; for reporting at least biennial
blood donation and none in 2009, annual donation and none since 2008, or
donation every few years and none since 2006; for reporting responding to 100%
emails and not replying to all of ours or reporting at least 95% responsiveness
and replying to fewer than 50% of ours.
More conservative measures of suspicious responding also show no
difference between the groups.
[67]
χ2 = 0.2, p = .89; χ2 = 0.0, p = .95.
[68]
Ethicists t = -2.4, p = .02; non-ethicist philosophers also t = -2.7, p = .01;
merged t = -3.6, p < .001.
[69]
Due to differences in denominator, non-philosophers’ suspicious responding
scores are not straightforwardly comparable to philosophers’. Only 17 non-philosophers showed at least two
suspicious responses: mean 3.2, vs. 2.8 for the remainder (t = 1.2, p = .23).
[70]
We choose self-reported membership because measured membership is unavailable
for non-philosophers. We choose
self-reported vote since many respondents would have to be excluded if we used
only measured vote rate, and we detected no pattern of bias in self-reported
voting. The donating blood measure
disadvantages those ineligible, but that should not affect the group comparison
since the rate of self-reported ineligibility is virtually identical among the
groups. Patterns of suspicious
responding are not included in the measure because of numerator differences between
philosophers and non-philosophers. Charitable behavior is excluded because the
self-report results went the opposite direction from the measured-behavior
results, problematizing the interpretation of both. Respondents missing any component (e.g.,
reporting “driver’s license not available”) are excluded from the analysis.
[71]
ANOVA, F = 1.6, p = .21.
[72]
SD = 1.2 for all groups, Bartlett’s test, p = .61.
[73]
t = 0.5, p = .59, SD = 1.4 for both groups.
[74]
ANOVA, F = 2.7, p = .07, SD = 0.9, 1.0, 1.0.
[75]
ANOVA, F = 12.8, p < .001, including only respondents who answered all nine
normative questions; pairwise Tukey comparisons finds ethicists and
non-ethicist philosophers both different from non-philosophers.
[76]
ANOVA, F = 4.8, p = .009, Tukey pairwise comparisons finds ethicists different
from non-philosophers.
[77]
All r’s were converted to Fisher’s zr, then averaged, then converted
back to r. Pairwise comparison of the
aggregate r’s, using Fisher’s zr conversion and geometric mean N’s,
found all p’s ≥ .48. For
between-group comparability, we excluded the honesty measure and used
self-reported society membership. To
include the zeros in the charity measure, we used the square-root
transformation (excluding the 500% outlier) rather than the logarithmic
transformation. For blood donation, we
used self-reported donation rates of at least every few years (excluding
ineligibles) as the behavioral measure.
Otherwise the behavioral measures were those with which we concluded the
corresponding sections.
[78]
Mean birth year 1953 for all three groups of recipients (ANOVA, F = 0.1, p =
.92).
[79]
Overall birth year difference t = 1.5, p = .13.
Mean birth year was 1955 for ethicist and non-ethicist philosopher
respondents and 1953 for non-philosopher respondents (ANOVA, F = 1.4, p =.26).
[80]
Mean birth year of those rating meat eating as bad 1958 vs. 1952 for not bad; t
= 4.1, p < .001. Pearson correlation
of age and measured vote rate for all recipients (square-root transformed), r =
.18, p < .001. Pearson correlation of
age and self-reported vote rate (square-root transformed), r = .19, p = .001. As a correction for multiple comparisons we
set alpha at .01 for statistical significance and .05 for marginality. Older respondents were marginally more likely
to rate low maternal contact as bad (mean birth year for bad 1954, for not bad
1957; t = -2.2, p = .03), marginally more likely to rate it bad not
consistently to respond to student emails (mean birth year for bad 1954, for
not bad 1959; t = -2.5, p = .015); and marginally less likely to rate it good
to give 10% to charity (mean birth year for good 1956, for not good 1951; t =
2.6, p = .011). They also showed a
statistically marginal trend toward reporting having given larger proportions
of their income to charity in 2008: Pearson correlation of age and
log-transformed charitable rate, r = .14, p = .02.
[81]
χ2 = 5.3, p = .02; χ2 = 29.4, p < .001.
[82]
Again setting alpha at .01 for a significant difference and .05 for a marginal
trend as a correction for multiple comparisons.
Three marginal trends emerged: 93% of women rated voting as good,
compared to 86% of men (χ2 = 5.3, p = .02); 66% rated not
keeping in monthly contact with one’s mother as bad, compared to 76% of men
(χ2 = 6.1, p = .013); and 75% of women reported being organ
donors, compared to 66% of men (χ2 = 4.6, p = .03). See the subsequent text for analysis of the
gender differences on vegetarianism.
[83]
χ2 = 28.3, p < .001.
[84]
χ2 = 13.0, p < .001;χ2 = 11.9, p =
.001;χ2 = 25, p = .11.
[85]
All three t’s ≥ 3.6, p’s < .001.
[86]
χ2 = 4.7, p = .03; χ2 = 0.0, p = .94; χ2
= 1.9, p = .17; overall 33% vs. 41%, χ2 = 2.8, p = .096.
[87]
The numbers meeting all three criteria are small, so exact percentages should
be treated cautiously, though the difference is extreme enough to be highly
statistically significant: 22/27 vs. 3/41, χ2 =38.5, p <
.001.
[88]
t = 0.5, p = .59.
[89]χ2
=0.0, p = .89, including only respondents for whom gender and birth year
information were available. Again, due
to the small number of young female philosophers (26), the exact percentage
should be treated cautiously: 95% CI for difference -18% to 21%.
[90]
These results are rather different from those to a similar question in the
PhilPapers survey by David Bourget and David Chalmers in November, 2009 (URL http://philpapers.org/surveys/). Differences in subject pool and in response
options might explain some of the difference in results.
[91]
N = 98 metaethicists, 156 normative ethicists, and 109 applied ethicists. Given the number of comparisons, we set the
alpha level for statistical significance at .01. Among the attitudinal questions, the lowest p
value we found was .04, with 84% of applied ethicists and 93% of other
ethicists rating 10% charitable donation as good. Among the behavioral measures, the lowest p
value was also .04, with 47% of metaethicists reporting having eaten the meat
of a mammal at their previous evening meal, compared to 32% of other
ethicists. On the broadest measure of
overall behavior – the second measure described in Section 13, including meat
eating, measured APA membership, and measured suspicious responding – the
metaethicists scored an average of 4.6, the normative ethicists an average of
4.7, and the applied ethicists an average of 4.7, out of 8.
[92]
Rating APA membership as good: virtue ethicists 59% vs. 80% of deontologists and
74% of consequentialists (χ2 = 8.8, p = .012); rating not
having an organ donor symbol as bad: virtue ethicists 48% vs. 65% for both
other groups (χ2 = 8.8, p = .03); rating blood donation as good
81% vs. 94% and 90% (χ2 = 6.6, p = .04). Because of the consistency of the trend we
interpret the p values as significant despite the multiple comparisons. All χ2’s in this note and the
next are 3x2.
[93]
Measured APA membership: virtue ethicists 58%, deontologists 65%,
consequentialists 74% (χ2 = 5.1, p = .08); organ donation: 58%
vs. 78% and 70% (χ2 = 6.7, p = .04); but blood donation since
2005 did not split in the direction predicted by expressed normative view: 14%
vs. 20% and 12% (χ2 = 1.5, p = .47). On the broadest summary measure (measure 2),
deontologists scored 4.9, consequentialists 4.6, and virtue ethicists 4.4 –
within statistical chance (ANOVA, F = 2.2, p = .11).
[94]
Rating meat eating as morally bad: consequentialists 58% vs. 53% for both other
groups (χ2 = 0.5, p = .79); reporting meat at least meal:
consequentialists 38% vs. deontologists 34% and virtue ethicists 38% (χ2
= 0.3, p = .87).
[95]
For help with survey design, many thanks to Ruth Chao, David Crow, Martin
Johnson, and the U.C. Riverside Survey Research Center. For useful comments and discussion, thanks to
audiences at University of Sydney, the American Philosophical Association,
CalTech, the Australasian Association of Philosophy, University of Nevada Las
Vegas, Oxford University, University of Edinburgh, University of Miami,
University of Arizona, University of Osnabrück, and The Splintered Mind blog,
and especially to P.J. Ivanhoe, Jean Kazez, Joshua Knobe, Edouard Machery,
Michael Ridge, and ****.